Philosophy of Science and the Quantitative-Qualitative Debates

Philosophy of Science and the Quantitative-Qualitative Debates

Evaluationand Pqram Planning, Vol. 18, No. 1, PP. 63-75. 1995 Copyright 0 1995 Elsevier Science Ltd Pergamon Printed in the USA. All rights resetved 0149-7189195 $9.50 + .OO 0149-7189(94)00050-6 PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND THE QUANTITATIVE-QUALITATIVE DEBATES: Thirteen Common Errors W~LLL+MR. SHADISH The University of Memphis ABSTRACT One of the most important benefits of the qualitative-quantitative &bate in evaluation has been the increased awareness it has brought evaluators about philosophy of science. But evaluators are rarely philosophers, and consequently their presentations of philosophical material may contain errors. This article highlights thirteen common errors of this kind, and discusses some implications of these errors for the quantitative-qualitative debate. What are the most important accomplishments in the first the near impossibility of justifying any particular method 30 years of program evaluation? To me, the introduction as being always and everywhere best. of qualitative methods into evaluation should certainly be Unfortunately, very few evaluators are philosophers by near the top of the list (Shadish, Cook, & Leviton, 1991). training. Most evaluators learned about these matters Without doubt, these methods have proven their utility to either by reading what other evaluators say about philoso- practicing evaluators, their distinctiveness to theorists, phy of science, or more rarely by reading original philo- and their attractiveness to readers of evaluation results. sophical works themselves. In my own work, I have Qualitative methods are here to stay, and evaluation is learned from both sources. In the process, however, I have much better for it. also learned that reading primary sources in philosophy is In the process of introducing these methods, many the- a far more reliable source of what philosophers say than is orists have also introduced arguments from philosophy of reading what evaluation theorists say philosophers say. science that explain why these methods ought to receive The discrepancies are often substantial. Hence the goal of more attention. This philosophical material is as welcome the present article is to correct 13 common errors about as the methods themselves, helping us to think more philosophy of science that seem to be prevalent in the clearly and completely about why we do what we do. For quantitative-qualitative debate today (see Phillips, 1990, example, as a result of these arguments, most evaluators for a similar work covering largely different ground). are more aware of the socially constructed nature of eval- I should begin, however, with a number disclaimers. uative knowledge, of the philosophical ambiguities that Fit, I do not purport to present any original philosophical necessarily surround any scientific methodology, and of research in this article; my own quasi-philosophical views The author thanks Lee Sechrest, who served as action editor for this article, and Terry Hedrick and Ernie House for providing helpful comments on previous drafts. Both Steve Fuller and Chip Reichardt made a number of detailed comments that they generously allowed me to incorporate directly into this article. Of course, none of these readers agreed with all the material in this manuscript. Requests for reprints should be sent to William R. Shadish, Department of Psychology, The University of Memphis, Memphis, TN 38152. 63 64 WILLIAM R. SHADISH are outlined elsewhere (e.g., Shadish, 1994). Rather, I sim- misstatements of its key tenets. Indeed, it is not always ply juxtapose some things said in the evaluation literature clear that evaluation theorists intend to use the term accu- against divergent descriptions of the same matters in phi- rately. Rather, the term has frequently become the lin- losophy of science. I hope the juxtaposition will raise guistic equivalent of “bad,” a rhetorical device aimed at enough concern in readers’ minds to reduce the frequency depriving one’s opponent of credibility by name-calling. with which these errors occur. Second, my aim is not to This is particularly true in the quantitative-qualitative criticize particular evaluation theorists. To the contrary, debate where some qualitative theorists are fond of those theorists who have written about these matters labelling all quantitative opponents as logical positivists. should be congratulated for stimulating all evaluators to But it is not limited to that debate. Logical positivism has read and think more about philosophy of science. Indeed, become the favorite way to characterize the “status quo” since I am not a philosopher myself, I will undoubtedly whenever a “new paradigm” is discussed in evaluation, make mistakes of my own in this article. But hopefully this including those discussions that claim to be integrating article will still advance the conceptual debate by correct- quantitative and qualitative positions. ing some of the more serious and obvious errors, by point- If one reads the evaluation literature, one can find ing to questions that can be further explored in the interest almost as many descriptions of logical positivism as there of accuracy, and in the end by making fewer mistakes than are evaluation theorists. In part this is understandable, for it corrects. Third, these errors are most commonly found in the roots of logical positivism go back hundreds of years, debates between quantitative and qualitative evaluators, so and much depends on the philosopher to whom one refers I will refer to that debate to illustrate these errors. But the (Bechtel, 1988). Still, the most common referent is usually errors are not limited to that context. Rather, the errors are to the Vienna Circle in Austria, and the Berlin School in made by evaluators of nearly all methodological and theo- Germany, in the early part of the 20th century. If one boils retical ilks. These errors come from an equal opportunity down their logical positivism to its essence, two character- demon, our own ignorance. Fourth, I apologize at the start istics are crucial. The “positivist” part of the label refers to for the jargon that is inevitably part of philosophical dis- the notion that knowledge should be based on direct expe- cussions. I try to keep the jargon to a minimum, and to rience; and the “logical” part invokes a commitment to the- explain it where it is used. But sometimes I introduce ory development using a rigorous procedural language terms (like relativism, or constructivism) simply to identi- such as symbolic logic. Knowledge comes either from fy certain alternatives that would take far more space than direct experience or indirectly from inferences from expe- I have here to discuss fully. I hope I have struck a reason- rience through the procedural language. able balance, however, so that the end result is understand- Most evaluation theorists describe the positivist part able. For evaluators who want to know more, excellent of the label accurately enough, although they often fail to introductions by philosophers are available (Bechtel, 1988; give due credit to logical positivists themselves for their Brown, 1977; Laudan, 1992; Phillips, 1987, 1990). own disputes about the extent to which knowledge really Finally, I do not extend this discussion to showing how can be grounded in experience. But few evaluation theo- each error might carry implications for the practice of rists even discuss the part of the label refering to logic. evaluation. Sometimes the implications are simple and This part refers to a commitment to an axiomatic account obvious (there is nothing wrong with talking about and of theory in which events are derived from laws (and investigating causes); but sometimes they are complex and other known facts) which are in turn derived from more subtle (whether or not experiments are about confirmation general theories. Logical positivists most often held out or discovery, a theory of when we should use experiments first-order predicate logic as the ultimate scientific lan- would depend on many more factors that I can cover here). guage for use in this process. But in spirit, they would Indeed, we err if we think that our practice ought to be accept any rigorous procedural language. Conversely, guided primarily by philosophy of science. Evaluation they generally distrusted ordinary natural language practice risks serious loss of contact with its political, because ordinary words carry too many stray meanings to social, and economic roots to the extent that it takes phi- be rigorous tools of scientific inquiry. losophy of science as a starting point for its practice. But If we were to acknowledge this part of logical posi- as an academic, I can afford the luxury of speculating on tivism, then we would be compelled to admit that no these more philosophical matters. Which I shall now do. evaluation theorist appears to be much of a logical posi- tivist, either today or in the past. After all, when was the last time that you saw symbolic logic on the pages of an COMMON ERROR #l: SOME EVALUATION evaluation journal or book? When has an evaluation the- THEORISTS ARE LOGICAL POSITIVISTS orist professed a desire to axiomatize any theory or eval- uation in terms other than ordinary natural language? Logical positivism is a phrase most evaluators recognize. Indeed, when has an evaluation theorist even contended But few evaluators know what it is; and there are many that some theory could be rationally reconstructed using Coounoo Errors 65 such logic? When was this even an issue for them? In searching for methods that would yield definitive scien- fact, all evaluations, and all evaluation theory, seem to be tific answers. One can find philosophers who believe that couched in ordinary natural language. And evaluators of we do not have an adequate account of science unless we all philosophical and methodological ilks routinely dis- have a formal account of the nature of explanation and cuss inferences from the data that are not rigorously justi- confirmation in science. These philosophers may fied through any neutral procedural language.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    13 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us