1 Epicureans & Stoics on Temporality 1. Who

1 Epicureans & Stoics on Temporality 1. Who

Dr. Sean Hannan MacEwan University January 2017 Epicureans & Stoics on Temporality 1. Who were the Epicureans? a. The Epicureans trace their lineage back (unsurprisingly) to Epicurus, a Greek thinker (can we say ‘philosopher?’) of the fourth and third centuries BCE. He seems to have died around 270 BCE, which would make him substantially younger than Aristotle. b. Like Plato, Aristotle, and others, Epicurus founded his own place of learning in Athens. His was known as the Garden (Kēpos). Much of what he taught has to be reconstructed via what was said of him by both his followers and his opponents. The Epicurean school can reductively be looked at in two of its subdisciplines: i. Epicurean ethics: The good life, for an Epicurean, would be ataraxia: the absence (or at least minimization) of fear and disturbance, especially agitation arising from the thought of one’s own death. This emphasis has often been mistaken for a wanton hedonism, which places pleasure-chasing at the summit of human life. But that’s not quite right. The Epicureans were still rationalists. The goal was to rationally parcel out one’s pleasures, so as to avoid pain and distress as much as possible, while also avoiding self- destruction via pleasure overload at any one moment. The Epicurean focus on pleasure was thus more therapeutic than libertine. ii. Epicurean physics: Far from remaining mere hedonists, the Epicureans developed their own robust view of the natural world. In that way, they did not blush at natural science as had Socrates. For the Epicureans, the universe was made up of only two things, as we’ll see: atoms and void. There were minimal, un-cuttable particles which made up the ultimate stuff of matter, and then also a great emptiness (kenon; inane) into which those atoms could plunge and collide with one another. This intermingling of atoms within the void was what constituted the baseline existence of all things. The basis for this atomic theory of the universe, while in many ways rationally formulated, ultimately rested on an empirical sense that there is always a smallest ‘something,’ beyond which human experience cannot pass. iii. The founding question here is then: how to relate Epicurus’ ethics with his physics? Does quasi-hedonistic pursuit of ataraxia go hand in hand with spatiotemporal atomism? Must it? Is the atomic worldview, with its naturalistic eschewing of divine intervention, meant to thrust us back upon our dire situation, wherein we are finite mortals caught up in a world beyond our imagining? Does Epicurean physics put us in the proper existential pose to appreciate their ethical, therapeutic teachings? 2. Who were the Stoics? a. The Stoics, like the Epicureans, find their origins in late fourth-century BCE Athens. Their purported founder, Zeno of Citium (not to be confused with the Eleatic Zeno!), can be seen as combining the Cynics’ view of ethics with a broader natural- scientific worldview. Here we are giving the Cynics (like Diogenes) credit for taking to its logical extreme the insight that virtue (‘being good’) is by far the most important thing in life. For the Cynics, this meant that it was morally laudable to give up all of the trappings of ‘civilized’ life in order to get at the purity of a virtuous existence. If that meant walking around the agora naked, so be it! 1 Dr. Sean Hannan MacEwan University January 2017 b. The Stoics modified this Cynical rigor in order to make it more accessible to a wider audience. They maintained the utter devotion to reason and nature—especially practical reason—while also including a broader application of theoretical reason. Stoic physics even equated the force of reason with that of a primordial fire, which gave birth to the universe as we know it and will later burn it all up again. Such conflagrations serve as the punctual nodes of cyclical history. The eternal return revolves and passes through the walls of eternal flame. These are the doctrines that would be passed down via later Greek Stoics like Chrysippus to the revived Roman Stoicism of Seneca and Marcus Aurelius. c. In competition with the Academy, the Lyceum, and the Garden, there was now also the Stoa Poikile—a covered, painted walkway that gave its name to Zeno’s movement. There, he taught his doctrines of rational fire and encouraged his students to pursue apatheia. Often caricatured as a cold-hearted form of unfeeling (‘apathy’), apatheia could more generously be described as allowing the power of reason to properly frame and contextualize the worldly events that affect us. A mind endowed with apatheia could rationally digest even the apparent ‘worst’ that life could throw at a person. d. As with the Epicureans, then, we see a sometimes curious blend of ethical and physical insights. Perhaps this can be profitably compared with Plato, whose Timaeus was a strangely cosmological sequel to his politics. The border between Nature and the Polis was rather fuzzy for these traditions. That seems less true of Aristotle, whose disciplinary boundaries usually remained firmer. (One exception to that might be the passage in the Physics where Aristotle allows his eyes to grow misty over the inevitability of phthora…) 3. Lucretius, De Rerum Natura a. Lucretius was a Roman poet and philosopher who flourished in the first half of the first century BCE. We don’t know as much about his life as we’d like, but we do know he remains by far the most famous exponent of Epicureanism during the late Republic. His only extant work is a long-form poem ‘on the nature of things,’ addressed to his patron Memmius. The goal, it seems, is to cure Memmius of the timor mortis by introducing him to the tenets of Epicureanism and ataraxia. Lucretius’ work were influential in the development of classical poetry, although perhaps less so in natural philosophy. Epicurean atomism did not become dominant, as Sorabji convincingly attests. Nevertheless, some continue to hold (tenuously) that the rediscovery of Lucretius in fifteenth-century Italy played a role in bringing scientific atomism back into the realm of plausibility. b. Book I i. Time 1. Sense-experience (sensus) is the bedrock standard of truth. Only on this empirical basis can reasoning (ratio) about non-perceptible things occur. 2. The testimony of both sense and reason is that there are only two ‘things’ in the universe: bodies (ultimately, atoms) and the inane void. 3. Nothing else gets to be a tertium genus—not even Time. 4. Time actually doesn’t even exist in its own right. 5. Time itself is an accident (eventum). 6. It is neither a substance nor even a property (coniunctum). 7. Time is the accident of what happens within it. 2 Dr. Sean Hannan MacEwan University January 2017 8. Temporal experience, too, is really only experience of movement. 9. There’s no such thing as a pure experience of time, sans movement- rest. 10. In conclusion: tempus per se non est. a. Contrast this with Aristotle, for whom the continuum (suneches) appears to be primary. Riffing peripatetically, we could posit that the continuum ‘is,’ whereas the segments of the continuum (P-P-F) are the proper ‘accidents’ here. ii. History 1. This has immediate consequences for history. 2. Properly speaking, historical happenings “are” not. 3. They are merely the accidents of long-past generations (saecla). 4. That is: they are ‘events’ (eventa) in a very special sense. 5. All of this is a reduction of being (what really is). 6. It reduces being to what is present (instet: what stands-in). 7. It depends on an experientially present moment. 8. Because only that moment can be the bedrock for being. 9. All accidents of time merely accrue to that bedrock. iii. Atomism 1. Lucretius concedes that experience seems fluid. 2. Experience suggests that Heraclitean flux rules the world. 3. All is ceaseless change without solidity. 4. However—reason steps in to tell us this is not the case. 5. (This is an interesting move for an Epicurean to make.) 6. (He allows reason to correct experience quite sternly here.) 7. Reason tells us that only small, solid, everlasting atoms allow us to divide up the universe and explain how its variety arises. 8. These atoms are the primordial seeds of all composite things. 9. There is no ex nihilo here. Nothing comes from nothing. 10. Instead, there must be an everlasting pool of atoms in the void. 11. They provide the raw material for the universe of things. iv. Infinity 1. Time, which is merely an accident, is somehow also infinite. 2. But within infinite time, nature sets many limits. 3. Nature sets a limit for the dissolution of bodies. (finis frangendi) 4. Nature also sets a limit for the temporal duration of composites. 5. The finis frangendi ensures that atoms exist as primordial seeds. 6. The finita tempora ensure that the pool of atoms is ever refilled. 7. These limits also ensure the predictability of the universe. 8. If there were no everlasting pool of the same atoms underlying everything, than anything could change into anything else at any time. 9. We’d no longer have certainty about future possibilities. 10. The generations (saecla) would stop being so repetitive. 11. Atomism, then, provides a regularization and a routine to the world. 12. It limits future potentiality and changeability. 13. Indeed: “nothing changes,” really, from an atomic perspective. v. Subatomic Particles 1. Atoms: un-cuttables. Can’t get smaller than that, right? 3 Dr. Sean Hannan MacEwan University January 2017 2. Wrong! There are minima: the smallest subatoms. 3. Atoms: smallest perceivable bodies; literally unbreakable.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    6 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us