Is Common Descent an Axiom of Biology?

Is Common Descent an Axiom of Biology?

Is Common Descent an Axiom of Biology? This discussion paper was written for the conference, “The Darwinian Paradigm: Problems and Prospects,” held June 22-25, 1993, at the Pajaro Dunes beach community on Monterey Bay, near Watsonville, California. The conference was organized by Phillip Johnson. Attendees included Doug Axe, Michael Behe, Walter Bradley, John Angus Campbell, William Dembski, Dean Kenyon, Stephen Meyer, Paul Nelson, David Raup, Siegfried Scherer, Jonathan Wells, and Kurt Wise. To: Pajaro Dunes Conference Participants From: Paul Nelson and Jonathan Wells Date: 15 June 1993 Re: Discussion paper for Topic Area I (homology, etc.) This paper is intended to highlight key points in the readings (being sent to the participants by Phil Johnson), and to suggest some general issues for discussion. The issues we raise do not, of course, exhaust the possibilities. The readings are: 1. Thomas Jukes and Syozo Osawa, "Recent Evidence for Evolution of the Genetic Code," in Evolution of Life, eds. S. Osawa and T. Honojo. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1991, pp. 79-95. 2. V. Louise Roth, "The Biological Basis of Homology," in Ontogeny and Systematics, ed. C.J. Humphries. New York: Columbia University Press, 1988, pp. 13-29. 3. G.P. Wagner, "The Biological Homology Concept," Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 20 (1989): 51-69. 4. E.B. Wilson, "The Embryological Criterion of Homology," Biological Lectures Delivered at the Marine Biological Laboratory of Wood's Holl, Summer Session of 1894. Boston: Ginn & Co., 1895. I. The Neo-Darwinian Explanation for Homology We start by reviewing some familiar ground. The conventional neo-Darwinian explanation for homology (call it the conventional explanation) is clearly outlined by Romer and Parsons: Homologous organs are those which are identical – the same – in the series of forms studied. But what do we mean by "the same"? One tends, unthinkingly, to believe that the same actual mass of material, the very same limb or leg or bone, has been handed down, generation to generation, like an heirloom. This is quite absurd, but such a concept has obviously influenced, unconsciously, the minds of many workers. 1 In reality, of course, every organ is re-created anew in every generation, and any identity between homologues is based upon the identity or similarity of the developmental processes which produce them. The development of the science of genetics has given us a firm base for the interpretation of these processes. They are controlled by hereditary units, the genes....If the genes remain unchanged from generation to generation, the organ produced will remain unchanged (apart from environmental effects upon an individual which may be obvious, but are not inherited by the next or later generations), and the homology is absolute. Changes, however, do occur in genes, as mutations; these mutations produces changes in the structures to which the genes give rise....In a sense, a study of organ homology is merely a study of phenomena produced by genes. If the genetic constitution of all animal types were well known, the determination of homology between structures might well rest upon the degree of identity of the genes concerned in their production. What then are the best criteria for the establishment of homology?...Best of all is similarity in developmental history. Embryologic processes in vertebrates tend to be conservative, and organs which are very different in the adult condition may reveal their homology through similarity in embryonic stages.1 The conventional explanation can be represented more schematically as follows: A. Main Principle: Descent with Modification (Material Continuity from a Common Ancestor) B. What Descends are Genes (Homologous Replicators) C. Genes Control Development (Homologous Developmental Processes and Patterns) D. Development Constructs Phenotypes (Homologous Structures) (Q.E.D. ) And the conventional explanation is often embedded in the following story. When Darwin arrived on the scene in the mid- nineteenth century, natural historians were puzzled by the remarkable patterns of similarity they had discovered, such as the pentadactyl limb or the vertebrate body plan. Darwin provided a material causal explanation for the origin of these patterns, in the principle of descent with modification from common ancestors (with all living things descending, ultimately, from a single common ancestor). After the discovery of the rules of inheritance in Mendelian genetics, the picture Darwin left unfinished was completed, and "the problem of homology" was solved – a major scientific advance gained by the Darwinian revolution. As Ronald Brady observes, We must remember that, for the minds of his contemporaries, much of the strength of Darwin's hypothesis lay in its ability to account for the patterns of 2 natural history....Since that time, one may well agree with Dobzhansky (1973) that "Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution," for without the theory of evolution we would stand again before the interlocking patterns of common plan, homology, hierarchy, ontogenetic parallelism and divergence, etc., without a causal hypothesis. The experience is now so distant that it may be difficult to imagine.2 Some elements of the Darwinian interpretation of homology, such as the theological suboptimality argument against the independent creation of homologous patterns, are more properly the bailiwick of Topic Area 4. Still, we note the following. "Nothing can be more hopeless," Darwin argues of the pentadactyl limb pattern, "than to attempt to explain this similarity of pattern...by utility or by the doctrine of final causes." Nowadays this has become, in Ayala's hands, for instance, "an engineer could design better limbs in each case"3, meaning, of course, a Really Competent Divine Engineer. We expect that John Campbell will have illuminating things to say about this aspect of Darwin's rhetorical program. And Paul Nelson will be bringing copies of his paper on evolutionary theological arguments. As far as Paul has been able to discover, the suboptimality of the pentadactyl limb pattern has never been empirically demonstrated, but merely assumed. Darwin's evidence for suboptimality, when the thread is wound to its end, turns out to be only Richard Owen's unhappiness with the pentadactyl pattern. The pattern squares...little," Owen opines, "with our idea of the simplest mode of effecting the purpose."4 The fact that Richard Owen would have designed animals differently is helpful, perhaps, for learning the content of Owen's mind – but says nothing about the optimality or suboptimality of actual tetrapod limbs. II. Problems with the Conventional Explanation of Von Baer's Laws, I: The Evolutionary Interpretation Now Brady implies that the patterns Darwin united by the theory of common descent really do "interlock," and that after Darwin, there is a kind of evidential inevitability in the matter, leaving reasonable investigators with only one conclusion to draw. Such massive congruence of morphology, embryology, and genetics can only be explained by material descent (whether the process was governed or mediated by a Creator is a separate question). There really is a tree of life, with a single root. But do the patterns interlock? That is, does a consistent mapping obtain between levels B, C, and D of the conventional explanation schema, in good accord with expectations generated by the theory of monophyletic descent (level A)? Those who enter very far into the subject will find an astonishing degree of confusion, and differences of opinion striking enough to awaken the philosopher of science in anyone. 3 Take, for instance, early embryonic similarity in the vertebrates. Ayala sketches the received view as follows: Vertebrates, from fishes through lizards to humans, develop in ways that are remarkably similar during early stages, but they become more and more differentiated as the embryos approach maturity. The similarities persist longer between organisms that are more closely related (man and monkey) than between those less closely related (man and shark). Common developmental patterns reflect evolutionary kinship.5 But this is simply not the case. The earliest developmental patterns in vertebrates appear quite diverse: Indeed, X. laevis [frog], G. domesticus [chicken], and M. musculus [mouse] are radically different in such fundamental properties as egg size, fertilization mechanisms, cleavage patterns, and morphogenetic movements. This presents us with a conundrum: If early embryogenesis is conservative [that is, functionally constrained; see below], how did such major changes in the earliest events of embryogenesis occur?6 In fact, the most obvious structural characteristics of either the eggs or the cleavage stages of a shark, a salmon, a frog, a bird, or a mammal are unique each to its own class, not generally shared. We would not consider them very much alike unless we had been taught so at a very early age....Each class of vertebrates (in mammals we might almost say each particular order) develops and then loses its own set of temporary structures like the parade ground "formations of maneuver" during this period. The plain fact is that evolutionary divergence has taken place at every stage in the life history, the earliest no less than the latest.7 Empirically speaking these embryologists are not even in hailing distance of Ayala. Nor is this unusual. The status of the evolutionary interpretation of von Baer's laws of embryonic similarity8 (the received view; see Ayala, above) remains unresolved nearly a century after the embryologist Adam Sedgwick urged that the interpretation "falls to the ground."9 Stephen Jay Gould, for instance, writes of "von Baer's triumph," claiming that "his laws, in refurbished evolutionary dress, are now more widely accepted than ever before."10 "These empirical laws," write Raff and kaufman, "retain their validity today and may be observed in operation in the development of any vertebrate."11 Peter Medawar argues that the laws (which he thinks are true) were important to the general acceptance of descent: There is an element of truth in the so-called law of recapitulation, and it's embodied in Von Baer's law.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    17 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us