A Situation Semantics Approach to the Analysis of Speech Acts 1

A Situation Semantics Approach to the Analysis of Speech Acts 1

A SITUATION SEMANTICS APPROACH TO THE ANALYSIS OF SPEECH ACTS 1 David Andreoff Evans Stanford University 1. INTRODUCTION One might wonder whether these supra-utterance modes should count as speech acts. Certainly. the term "spcech act'" has ffaditionally been used in During thc past two decades, much work in linguistics has focused on reference to single sentences or to certain classes of non-scntenciaJ sentences as minimal units of communication, and the project of rigorously expressions which have single utterance indcpcndcncc in discourse (e.g. characterizing the structure of sentences in natural language has met with Hello). But consider again the traditional definition, paraphrasing Scarle some succcss. Not surprisingly, however, sentcnce grammars have (1969:4gff), a speech act is the use of an utterance directed at an addreasce contributed little to the analysis of discourse, Human discourse consists not in the scrvicc of a set of intentions, namely, just of words in sequences, hut of words in sequences directed by a speaker 1.) thc intention to producc a certain illocutionary effect in the to an addressee, used to represent situations and to reveal intentions. Only addressee, when the addressee has apprehcndcd both these aspects of the message 2.) the intention to produce this effect by getting the addressee to communicated can the message be interpretecL recognize the intention to produce the effect, and 3.) thc retention to produce this recognition by means of the addrcsaee's The analysis of discourse that emerges from Austin (1962), grounded in a knowicdge of the rules governing the utterance. theory of action, takes this view as ccntral, and thc concept of thc speech act follows naturally. An utterance may have a conventional meaning, but There is nothing in this characterization that requires that utterance be the interpretation of the actual meaning of the utterance as it is used in understood as scntencc. "ll~e crucial point is that the utterance (of whatever discourse depends on evaluating thc utterance in the context of the set of length) serve the set of intentions represented by 1.) - 3.). A valid speech intentions which represcnt the illocutionary mode of its presentation. Put act can bc regarded as defining an illocntionary mode which is govcrnod by another way (paraphrasing Searle (1975:3)), the speaker's intention is to conventions which constrain thc sorts of interpretations that can be givcn to produce understanding, consisting of the knowledge of conditions on the utterances which occur within that mode (including our judgmcnts un their speech act being pcrformed. appropriateness). Thcsc convcnUons also dcfinc the conditions that must be met for thc targct cffect to bc achieved, If we are to take scrionsly Scarle's (1969:16) assertion that "the unit of linguistic communication is not ... the symbol, word, or sentence, ... but Thus for the utterance / will be home by noon to count as a promise (and rather thc production or the issuance of thc symbol, word or sentence in the not. say. as a prediction), it must bc viewed as an utterance iasucd in the performance of the spcech act." then wc should be able to find some formal illocutionary mode of promising, wllich not only defineS ccrtain well- method of characterizing speech acts in discourse. Unfortunately, linguists formcdncss conditions on the utterance itself (making statemcnt,s in the past have too often employed speech acts as taxonomic convonicnces, as in Dora tense -- e.g. ! war home by noon .- impossible as direct speech act (1977). Labor and Fanshel (1977), and elscwhcre, without attempting to give anything more than a descriptive definition. Only in the atlJficial promises2), but also givcs the criteria which determine whether the act is intelligencc literature, notably in the work of Allcn, Bruce, Cohcn, and successful (including the felicity conditions, e¢.). Pcrrauh (e.g. Allen (1979), Bruce and Newman (1978). Cohen and Perrault (1979), Cohen (1978). Perrault, Allen, and Cohcn (1978)), does onc find an Similarly, for a series of utterances to count as a refutation, they must be attempt to dcfinc spcech acts in terms of more gcncral processes, here seen as operating in the illocutionary mode of rcfutation, as for example, in specifically, opcrations on planning networks. thc text below: 2. TYPES OF SPEECH ACTS (3) You have stated that 2 + 2 = 3. But take any two individual objects and any other two individual objectx and place them in a row. Then count them. say. from left to righL What do you get? A great problem for the computational linguist attempting to find a formal representation for speech acts is that thc set of speech acts does not map Not 3 but 4. Therefore; 2 + 2 cannot equal 3. uniformly onto the set of sentences. In terms of "guodncss of fit" with We cannot interpret any of these utterances accurately unless we recognize sentences, sevcral types of speech acts can be described. One type, the so- that each contributes to the achievement of a focused goal, viz. a refiJtadon. called pcrformatives, including ASSERT, DECLARE, etc.. can be ¢ffected Once that intention is recognized, appropriatenc-ss and well-formodness in a single utterance. But even some of these can undcrgo further conditions can be applied to the text; and the success of the act can he decomposition. For example, assuming.that the usual felicity conditions measured against the set of criteria which are relevant to refutations, hold (of. Searte (1969:54f0), both (1) and (2) below can count as an including the usual felicity conditions, but also specific conditions on the apology, though neither sentence in (2) alone has the effect which their production of factual evidence and the demonstration of contradiction. combination achieves. Following this new characterization of speech acts, yet another type can be (1) 1 apologize for what I did. described, operating not at the uttcrancc level, or the supra-utterancc level, (2) I did a terrible thing. I'm very sorry. but at the sub-uttcrancc level. As an illustration of the phcnomcnon involvcd, consider thc following uncxccptionable utterance: In (2), the first sentence contributes to the effect of an apology only to the extent that an addressee can infer that it is intended as part of an apology. (4) 1 tom the guy at the door to watch out, but he wouldn't listen. The second sentence, which makes overt the expression of contrition, also exp~sses the sinccrity which is prerequisite for a felicitouS apology. But its The sccond refcrence to the guy of the first clause is made via the success, too. depends on an int'crence by tile addressec that it is intended as anaphoric pronoun he. But suppose, instead, a definite referring expression part of an apology. If the addressee cannot make that inference -- because, wcre used. Consider thc following: for cxamplc, the address¢c hctieves that the speakcr is speaking sarcastically -- the effect of the apology is lost not only for the second (5) I told the guy at the door to watch out, but the person wouldn't listen. sentence, but for the first as well. In this case, the illocutionary effect APOI,OGIZE can be regarded as supra-scmcntial, though, as in (1). appropriate single scntences can be used to achieve its effect. The person is a distinctly odd corefcrent, and seems inappropriate 3. An examination of this context reveals that the only definite 4 referring There are other types of speech acts, however, that cannot bc performed in expressions which caterer felicitously are pronomin;d epithets, such as the single utterances, but require several or even many utterances. For idiot, the fool• etc.; descriptions which can be given an interpretation as example. DEFEND (as in a lawyer's action on ~half of his client), derogatives, such as the saphomore; and expressions whose literal REFUTE (as in polemical argumentation) and PROVE (as in demonstraung interpretation contributes some sense of explanation to the situation being effccm from specific causcs) cannot be cffected as pcrfnrmatives: one represented -- viz. thaL though warned, the guY at the door didn't heed the cannot make a refutation by uttering the words. I refute ,V, as one might warning -- as in the deafmute. make an assertion by uttering thc words, I a.~ert X. 113 It can be shown that the principle involved is a speech act-like There are many interesting details to this model which must be ignored in a phenomenon. First. it can be noted that the choice nn_.~t to use the paper of this scope, but several ob~rvations relevant to speech acts can be unmarked corefercnt, he. signals that the speaker has some special intention made, in mind. Second. following a suggestion in Balinger (1977:7ff). it can be argued that a repeated definite description functions not only to refei" but First. this model accommodates the distinction made by most speech act also to characterize the referent as having the sense of the definite th¢orist.s between what a speaker says - the locutionary act -- and what a description. Finatly. it can be shown that all the acceptable definite speaker intends to communicate (or means) - the illocutionary act-/. This descriptions in this context can be interpreted uniformly as offering an distinction is rcpeated and coptt)red hcre in the treatment of the actual explanation5 for the failure to listen expressed by the second clause. discourse as a oair of sets of situation-types. One gives the set of situation- types of the text (written or spoken) -- st - and can be regarded as Note that the choice of coreferent in the case of the use of a definite representing the Iocutionary aspect of the act. The other gives the set of referring expre~on is not.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    4 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us