Chapter 3: Relations and Functions Proof

Chapter 3: Relations and Functions Proof

Theorem 3P ≡ Elements of Set Theory Let be an equivalence relation on a nonempty set A. The quotient set A=≡ = f[x]: x 2 Ag is a partition of A. Chapter 3: Relations and Functions Proof. 1 For any x; y 2 A, by Proposition 3.13 (iii), January 28 & 30, 2014 [x] 6= [y] =) [x] \ [y] = ;: [ 2 A = [x]. Indeed, [x] = fa 2 A : x ≡ ag⊆ A for any x 2 A, which x2A [ Teacher: Fan Yang leads to [x] ⊆ A. x2A [ On the other hand, A ⊆ [x] since x2A [ [ y 2 A =) y 2 [y] ⊆ [x] =) y 2 [x]: x2A x2A 1/36 2/36 The converse of the preceding theorem also holds: Theorem 3.16 Let Π be a partition of a nonempty set A. The relation ≡ defined as follows is an equivalence relation on A: for any x; y 2 A, x ≡ y () there exists X 2 Π such that x; y 2 X: X Y Functions Z Proof. By definition, ≡ is clearly reflexive and symmetric. It remains to show that ≡ is transitive. For any x; y; z 2 A such that x ≡ y and y ≡ z, by the definition of ≡, there exist X; Y 2 Π such that x; y 2 X and y; z 2 Y : Hence y 2 X \ Y 6= ;, which implies X = Y as Π is a partition. It then follows that x; z 2 X = Y , thereby x ≡ z. 3/36 4/36 (x1; x2) (y1; y2) (z1; z2) Definition 3.17 A function is a binary relation F such that for each x 2dom F, there is The squaring function f : R ! R is defined as f (x) = x2. The action of a unique y such that (x; y) 2 F. f on particular elements of R can be described by writing p The unique y is called the value of F at x, denoted byF (x). −2 7! 4; 2 7! 2; 2 7! 4; 3 7! 9; etc. If dom F = X and ran F ⊆ Y , then we write F : X ! Y and say that F is Each individual action can be represented by an ordered pair: a function from X into Y , or that F maps X into Y. p (−2; 4); ( 2; 2); (2; 4); (3; 9); etc. X Y X Y The set y1 y1 2 F = f(x; y) 2 R × R j y = x g x1 y2 x1 y2 x2 y3 x2 y3 of all such ordered pairs adequately represents the squaring function x3 y4 x3 y4 f , and is called the graph of f . In set theory, we simply take this set F y5 y5 of ordered pairs to be the function f . F R Clearly, the set F ⊆ R × R is a relation such that for any x 2dom F, there is a unique y such that (x; y) 2 F. For example: The relation F = f(x; y) 2 R × R j y = x2g is a function, + dom F = R and ran F = R [ f0g. We write F : R ! R. The relation R = f(x; y) 2 R × R j x2 + y 2 = 4g is not a function, 5/36 since e.g., (0; 2); (0; −2) 2 R. 6/36 The domain of a function can be a set of ordered pairs or n-tuples. For Definition 3.19 example, addition is a function + : R × R ! R. In this case, in place of Let F : X ! Y be a function from X into Y . +((a; b)), we write either +(a; b) or a + b. If ran F = Y , then we say that F is surjective or F is a function from X ontoY. Fact 3.18 If for any x ; x 2 X, If F and G are functions for which dom F = dom G and 1 2 x1 6= x2 =) F(x1) 6= F(x2); F(x) = G(x) then we say that F is one-to-one or injective. for every x 2 dom F, then F = G. If F is both surjective and injective, then F is called a bijection. Proof. Indeed, by the definition of functions, we have that X Y X Y X Y y (x; y) 2 F () x 2 dom F and y = F(x) 1 x1 y21 x1 y1 x1 y1 () x 2 dom G and y = G(x) (by assumption) x2 y3 x2 y2 x2 y2 x y x y x y () (x; y) 2 G: 3 42 3 3 3 3 y5 y4 F F F Hence F = G. surjective injective bijection 7/36 8/36 (x1; x2) (y1; y2) (z1; z2) Note: A function F : X ! Y is surjective iff for each y 2 Y , there exists Definition 3.20 x 2 X such that F(x) = y. A relation R is said to be single-rooted iff for each y 2 ranR, there is only one x such that xRy. For example: Consider the function F : R ! R, defined as F(x) = x2. X Y + y1 F is not surjective, since ran F = R [ f0g 6= R. x1 y2 F is not injective, since e.g. F(2) = 4 = F(−2). x2 y3 x3 y4 3 Consider the function G : R ! R, defined as G(x) = x . y p 5 G is surjective, since for each y 2 R, we have that G( 3 y) = y. R 3 3 not single-rooted G is injective, since G(x1) = G(x2) =) x1 = x2 =) x1 = x2. Thus G is a bijection. Clearly, if F is a function, then F is single-rooted iff F is one-to-one. 9/36 10/36 Theorem 3K Definition 3.21 Let F be a relation. Let F be an arbitrary relation, and A a set. (a)F [A [ B] = F[A] [ F[B]. The restriction of F to A is the set (b)F [A \ B] ⊆ F[A] \ F[B]. Equality holds if F is single-rooted. F A = f(x; y) j xFy ^ x 2 Ag: (b)F [A] − F[B] ⊆ F[A − B]. Equality holds if F is single-rooted. The image of A under F is the set F[A] = ran (F A) = fy j 9x 2 A(xFy)g: X Y x y In particular, if F is a function, then F[A] = fF(x) j x 2 Ag. 1 1 y2 x2 y X Y X Y 3 a0 a0 x3 y4 0 a1 0 a1 F 1 a2 1 a2 2 a3 2 a3 Proof. (a). y 2 F[A [ B] () 9x 2 A [ B s.t. xFy a a 3 4 3 4 () (9x 2 A s.t. xFy ) or (9x 2 B s.t. xFy) F F () y 2 F[A] or y 2 F[B] () y 2 F[A] [ F[B]: 11/36 12/36 Definition 3.22 Let F be a relation. The inverse of F is the set (b). y 2 F[A \ B] () 9x 2 A \ B s.t. xFy F −1 = f(y; x) j xFyg: =) (9x 2 A s.t. xFy) and (9x0 2 B s.t. x0Fy) () y 2 F[A] and y 2 F[B] Note: (F −1)−1 = F () y 2 F[A] \ F[B]: In general, even if F is a function, F −1 is not necessarily a If F is single-rooted, then in the second line of the above expression, function, but F −1 is a single-rooted relation, i.e., for any x = x0, which means that the second arrow is reversible. x 2 ran F −1, there is only one y such that yF −1x. (c). y 2 F[A] − F[B] () y 2 F[A] and y 2= F[B] Since the inverse of a function is always single-rooted, the following () (9x 2 A s.t. xFy) and (:9x 2 B(xFy)) corollary is an immediate consequence of the Theorem 3K. =) 9x 2 A − B s.t. xFy Corollary 3L () y 2 F[A − B]: For any function G and sets A, B: If F is single-rooted, then the thrid arrow is reversible. (a)G −1[A [ B] = G−1[A] [ G−1[B]. (b)G −1[A \ B] = G−1[A] \ G−1[B]. (b)G −1[A] − G−1[B] = G−1[A − B] 13/36 14/36 0 Definition 3.23 Since F is a function, we derive that y = y . Furthermore, since G is a function, yGz and yGz0 implies that z = z0, as desired. Let F; G be arbitrary relations. The composition of F and G is the set G ◦ F = f(x; z) j 9y(xFy ^ yGz)g: For any x 2 X, we have that (x; F(x)) 2 F and (F(x); G(F(x))) 2 G, thus (x; G(F(x))) 2 G ◦ F, which implies that G ◦ F(x) = G(F(x)), as X Y Z G ◦ F is a function. y1 z1 x1 z2 Theorem 3I x2 y2 z3 x3 For any relations F and G, y3 z4 (G ◦ F)−1 = F −1 ◦ G−1: F G Proof. For any ordered pair (z; x), Theorem 3H If F : X ! Y and G : Y ! Z are functions, then G ◦ F : X ! Z is a (z; x) 2 (G ◦ F)−1 () (x; z) 2 G ◦ F function, and G ◦ F(x) = G(F(x)) for all x 2 X. () xFy ^ yGz; for some y − − Proof. We first check that G ◦ F is a function. Suppose that x(G ◦ F)z () yF 1x ^ zG 1y; for some y 0 0 and x(G ◦ F)z .

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    9 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us