Distance Semantics for Relevance-Sensitive Belief Revision

Distance Semantics for Relevance-Sensitive Belief Revision

Distance Semantics for Relevance-Sensitive Belief Revision Pavlos Peppas Samir Chopra Norman Foo Dept of Business Administration Dept of Computer and Knowledge Systems Group University of Patras Information Science School of Computer Science 265 00 Patras, Greece Brooklyn College of the and Engineering [email protected] City University of New York University of New South Wales Brooklyn, NY 11210, USA Sydney, NSW 2052, Australia [email protected] [email protected] Abstract is not fully captured by the AGM paradigm. To remedy this shortcoming, Parikh introduced an additional axiom, named Possible-world semantics are provided for Parikh’s (P), as a supplement to the AGM postulates. Loosely speak- relevance-sensitive model for belief revision. Having ing, axiom (P) says that when new information ϕ is received, Grove’s system-of-spheres construction as a base, we only part of the initial belief set K will be affected; namely consider additional constraints on measuring distance the part that shares common propositional variables with the between possible worlds, and we prove that, in the pres- minimal language of ϕ. Parikh’s approach is also known as ence of the AGM postulates, these constraints character- the language splitting model. ize precisely Parikh’s axiom (P). These additional con- straints essentially generalize a criterion of similarity Although axiom (P) is just a first step towards captur- that predates axiom (P) and was originally introduced ing the role of relevance in belief revision 1, Parikh’s work in the context of Reasoning about Action. A by-product has received considerable attention since the publication of of our study is the identification of two possible read- (Parikh 1999) (see for example (Chopra & Parikh 1999), ings of Parikh’s axiom (P), which we call the strong and (Chopra & Parikh 2000), (Chopra, Georgatos, & Parikh the weak versions of the axiom. An interesting feature 2001)). Yet, despite all the research on axiom (P), no se- of the strong version is that, unlike classical AGM be- lief revision, it makes associations between the revision mantics for it have yet been formulated. This is the gap that policies of different theories. the present article aims to fill. We examine new constraints on systems-of-spheres and, building on Grove’s result, we prove that in the presence of the AGM postulates, axiom (P) is sound and complete with respect to these new semantic Introduction constraints. Much of the work in the field of Belief Revision is based on What is particularly pleasing about our result is that the the classical work of Alchourron, Gardenfors and Makin- new constraints on systems of spheres are in fact not new at son, (Alchourron, Gardernfors, & Makinson 1985), that has all; they essentially generalize a very natural condition that given rise to a formal framework for studying this process, predates axiom (P) and has been motivated independently by commonly referred to as the AGM paradigm. Within the Winslett in the context of Reasoning about Action (Winslett AGM paradigm there are two constituents that are of partic- 1988). This connection between Belief Revision with Rea- ular interest for this paper. The first is the set of rationality soning about Action further confirms intuitions about the re- postulates for belief revision, known as the AGM postulates lationship between the two areas (see (Peppas & Wobcke (Alchourron, Gardernfors, & Makinson 1985). The second 1992), (Peppas 1994), and (Peppas, Foo, & Nayak 2000)). is a special kind of preorder on possible worlds, called a sys- tem of spheres, based on which Grove defined a constructive In the course of formulating semantics for axiom (P) we model for belief revision; Grove has shown in (Grove 1988) observed that there are in fact two possible readings of this that the AGM postulates are sound and complete with re- axiom, which we call the strong and the weak versions of spect to his system-of-spheres semantics. (P). We present both these versions herein and we show that the strong version of (P) brings with it a new feature in the Studying the AGM paradigm, Parikh (Parikh 1999) ob- picture of classical AGM revision: it makes associations be- served that is it rather liberal in its treatment of the notion of tween the revision policies of different theories. relevance. More precisely, Parikh argues that during belief revision a rational agent does not change her entire belief The outline of the paper is as follows. We first present corpus, but only the portion of it that is relevant to the new some background material on the AGM paradigm and the information. This intuition of local change, Parikh claims, 1Work on relevance in general in Artificial Intelligence has been Copyright c 2004, American Association for Artificial Intelli- ongoing for a while. A comprehensive collection of papers dealing gence (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. with relevance could be found in (AIJ 1997). KR 2004 319 language splitting model (first three sections). The crucial cussion, we often project operations defined earlier for the axiom (P) is then examined in greater detail to fully flesh entire language L, to one of its sublanguages L . When this out its possible readings (4th section). We proceed with the happens, all notation will be subscripted by the sublanguage formulation of semantics for axiom (P). For ease of expo- L . For example, for a set of sentences Γ ⊂L, the term sition and clarity, we start by focusing on the special case CnL (Γ) denotes the logical closure of Γ in L . Similarly, of “opinionated” agents, that is, agents whose belief set is a [Γ]L denotes the set of all maximally consistent supersets of consistent complete theory (5th section). Then we consider Γ in L . When no subscript is present, it is understood that the general case of incomplete theories (6th section). The the operation is relevant to the original language L. last section contains some concluding remarks. The AGM Paradigm Formal Preliminaries Much research in belief revision is based on the work of Al- Throughout this paper we work with a finite set of propo- chourron, Gardenfors and Makinson (Alchourron, Gardern- sitional variables P = {p1,...pm}. We define L to be the fors, & Makinson 1985), who have developed a research propositional language generated from P (using the stan- framework for this process, known as the AGM paradigm. dard boolean connectives ∧, ∨, →, ¬ and the special sym- In this section we shall briefly review two of the main mod- bols , ⊥) and governed by classical propositional logic . els for belief revision within the AGM paradigm; the first is A sentence ϕ ∈Lis contingent iff ϕ and ¬ϕ. For a based on a set of rationality postulates, and the second on a set of sentences Γ of L, we denote by Cn(Γ) the set of all preorder on worlds known as a system of spheres. logical consequences of Γ, i.e., Cn(Γ) = {ϕ ∈L: Γ ϕ}. Cn(ϕ ,ϕ ,...,ϕ ) ϕ We shall often write 1 2 n , for sentences 1, The AGM Postulates ϕ2,...,ϕn, as an abbreviation of Cn({ϕ1,ϕ2,...,ϕn}). A theory T of L is any set of sentences of L closed under In the AGM paradigm, belief revision is modeled as a func- , i.e., T = Cn(T ). In this paper we focus only on consistent tion ∗ mapping a theory T and a sentence ϕ to the theory theories. Hence from now on, whenever the term “theory” T ∗ϕ. In this paper we assume that the theory T and the sen- appears unqualified, it is understood that it refers to a con- tence ϕ are individually consistent. Alchourron, Gardenfors, sistent theory. We denote the set of all consistent theories and Makinson have proposed the following set of postulates of L by KL. A theory T of L is complete iff for all sen- for belief revision: tences ϕ ∈L, ϕ ∈ T or ¬ϕ ∈ T . We denote the set of all consistent complete theories of L by ML. In the context of (K*1) T ∗ ϕ is a theory of L. systems of spheres, consistent complete theories essentially (K*2) ϕ ∈ T ∗ ϕ. play the role of possible worlds. Following this convention, in the rest of the article we use the terms “possible world” (K*3) T ∗ ϕ ⊆ T + ϕ. (or simply “world”) and “consistent complete theory” inter- (K*4) If ¬ϕ ∈ T then T + ϕ ⊆ T ∗ ϕ. changeably. For a set of sentences Γ of L, [Γ] denotes the set of all consistent complete theories of L that contain Γ. (K*5) T ∗ ϕ = L iff ¬ϕ. Often we use the notation [ϕ] for a sentence ϕ ∈L,asan (K*6) If ϕ ↔ ψ then T ∗ ϕ = T ∗ ψ. [{ϕ}] T abbreviation of . For a theory and a set of sentences T ∗ (ϕ ∧ ψ) ⊆ (T ∗ ϕ)+ψ Γ of L, we denote by T +Γthe closure under of T ∪ Γ, (K*7) . i.e., T +Γ=Cn(T ∪ Γ). For a sentence ϕ ∈Lwe often (K*8) If ¬ψ ∈ T ∗ ϕ then (T ∗ ϕ)+ψ ⊆ T ∗ (ϕ ∧ ψ). write T + ϕ as an abbreviation of T + {ϕ}. In the course of this paper, we often consider sublan- Systems of Spheres guages of L. Let P be a subset of the set of proposi- P tional variables P .ByL we denote the sublanguage of Apart from axiomatic approaches to belief revision, a num- L defined over P . In the limiting case where P is empty, ber of explicit constructions for this process have been pro- P we take L to be the language generated by , ⊥ and the posed. One popular construction is that proposed by Grove boolean connectives.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    10 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us