Introduction to the Elgar Companion to Economics and Philosophy John B

Introduction to the Elgar Companion to Economics and Philosophy John B

Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Economics Faculty Research and Publications Economics, Department of 1-1-2004 Introduction to The Elgar Companion to Economics and Philosophy John B. Davis Marquette University, [email protected] Alain Marciano Université de Reims Champagne Ardenne Jochen Runde University of Cambridge Published version. "Introduction," in The Elgar Companion to Economics and Philosophy. Eds. John B. Davis, Alain Marciano and Jochen Runde. Chelthenham: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2004: xii-xxvii. DOI. © 2004 Edward Elgar Publishing. Used with permission. Introduction John Davis, Alain Marciano and Jochen Runde The closing decades of the twentieth century saw a dramatic increase in interest in the role of philosophical ideas in economics. The period also saw a significant expansion in scholarly investigation into the different connections between economics and philosophy, as seen in the emergence of new journals, professional associations, conferences, seminar series, websites, research networks, teaching methods, and interdisciplinary collaboration. One of the results of this set of developments has been a remarkable distillation in thinking about philosophy and economics around a number of key subjects and themes. The goal of this Companion to Economics and Philosophy is to exhibit and explore a number of these areas of convergence. The volume is accordingly divided into three parts, each of which highlights a leading area of scholarly concern. They are: political economy conceived as political philosophy, the methodology and epistemology of economics, and social ontology and the ontology of economics. The authors of the chapters in the volume were chosen on the basis of their having made distinctive and innovative contributions to their respective areas of expertise. In addition, authors were asked to not only survey the state of the field as they saw it, but also provide statements of their own positions and their perspectives on the field in question and its possible direction of development in the future. We thus hope this volume will serve not only as an introduction to the field, but also stimulate further work and thinking concerning the questions it investigates. Political economy conceived as political philosophy The essays in the first part of this Companion investigate the idea of economics or political economy as political philosophy. This last term should not to be understood in the pejoratively restrictive sense of Rosenberg’s (1992) definition of economics as mathematical political science. Rather, it should be taken to refer to the use of specific (namely economic) tools to understand the conditions of social order. This perspective harks back to the founders of economics and their conception of the discipline. Of course some would argue that more than two hundred years of scientific research have carried the discipline away from this conception. In fact, however, and as the issues discussed in the chapters in this section show, the distance that separates political economy in its recent developmentsJohn B. Davis, Alain from Marciano its origins and is Jochen not that Runde large. - 9781840649642 Downloaded from Elgar Online at 07/14/2014 11:11:59AM xii via free access MMarcianoarciano 0000 pprelimsrelims xxiiii 227/8/047/8/04 112:56:112:56:11 ppmm Introduction xiii Regarding political economy as a form of political philosophy is not to deny its existence as a self-standing scientific discipline. Political economy is indeed a separate science in its own right and, in the opening chapter on ‘Natural Law, Natural History and the Foundations of Political Economy’, José Luìs Cardoso shows how it came to be so. Cardoso’s argument proceeds in two stages that correspond to two distinct but complementary developments in the eighteenth century. The first of these was the identification of an object interesting and important enough to require analysis over and above that already provided within the framework of the philosophy of natural law. Social and economic organisation thus came to be viewed as parts of the natural order. The second development was a recognition of the need for some form of scientific method in terms of which the analysis would be conducted. Here, according to Cardoso, political economy was deeply influenced by the growing stature of sciences that aimed to uncover the laws that governed the functioning of the natural world. Natural history, the most authoritative field of knowledge in the eighteenth century, along with the conceptual constructions of the natural sciences, accordingly came to provide the tools with which political economy was able to establish itself as a science. The three chapters that follow, by Alain Marciano, Shaun Hargreaves Heap and Bruno Frey and Mathias Benz respectively, discuss the virtues and limitations of the mainstream (neoclassical) economic model of the human agent, and the potential fruitfulness of a more refined representation. The objective is not, as Hargeaves Heap makes clear, to suggest that people never act in accordance with the assumptions of mainstream rational choice theory. Rather, it is to show that the highly stripped down psychology of the standard model of the economic agent is too thin to give an adequate account of people’s actions in all possible walks of life. As Frey and Benz explain, this model is a relatively recent consequence of economists’ efforts to rid the discipline of all traces of psychology, a contention well supported by Marciano’s demonstration that the conception of economic man adopted by the founding fathers of political economy was indeed considerably richer than it is now. As Marciano describes it, the rejection of Cartesian rationalism in favour of empiricism by Scottish Enlightenment authors such as Hume and Smith, led naturally to a theory of man limited in his cognitive abilities, whose knowledge would always be highly subjective and situation-dependent. The central message in Hargreaves Heap’s chapter on ‘Economic rationality’ is the need to pay attention to intersubjectively shared beliefs, particularly when attempting to understand behaviour that seems resistant to the standard model of economic agency. In many situations, according to Hargreaves Heap, individual agents are not driven solely by instrumental reason and the direct satisfaction they might derive from the outcome of any action, but also by the senseJohn of B.self-respect Davis, Alain they Marciano achieve and fromJochen knowing Runde - that9781840649642 their actions reflect well Downloaded from Elgar Online at 07/14/2014 11:11:59AM via free access MMarcianoarciano 0000 pprelimsrelims xxiiiiii 227/8/047/8/04 112:56:112:56:11 ppmm xiv The Elgar companion to economics and philosophy upon them. The difficulty this raises is that even if the desire for self-respect is regarded as a kind of preference, self-respect does not fit into the analytical framework of the standard rational choice model. This is because people’s judgements regarding what actions reflect well on them cannot be decided in isolation, namely without reference to the beliefs and values of other members of the community. And if so, it then it becomes necessary to analyse how individuals acquire and share beliefs about what is worthy. Obviously, these questions go beyond the boundaries of the rational choice model, and require input from other disciplines. Hargreaves Heap points out that psychology offers some relevant insights here, especially about cognitive dissonance and intrinsic/ extrinsic motivation. Frey and Benz, in their essay ‘From Imperialism to Inspiration: A Survey of Economics and Psychology’, also argue that economists can no longer rely only on an approach to human behaviour based on the model of the ‘homunculus economicus’. They too observe that there are many forms of human behaviour that are in conflict with the assumptions of, and therefore incomprehensible within, the framework of the standard model. In particular, Frey and Benz point out that, in contrast to the standard model, people face cognitive limits and are emotionally constrained, are not systematically egoistic in their behaviour, and are not committed to acting under the constraints of the material elements of their material utility function. The suggested remedy is that economists might draw on psychology to ‘inspire’ them out of the current impasse. But again, Frey and Benz are not proposing that economics be replaced by psychology. They continue to regard the standard model of the rational economic agent as a consistent general framework against which the insights of psychology, which ‘consists of a large number of partial theories and special effects, which are more or less isolated from each other’, may be thrown into sharper relief. A more refined, ‘inspired’ conception of economic man necessarily leads to normative implications in relation to the nature, the scope and the role of institutions. For example, in his essay entitled ‘The historical and philosophical foundations of new political economy’, Marciano shows that sympathy is a necessary condition for successful co-ordination, although not sufficient to order large and open societies. Therefore, even if spontaneously emerging conventions play an important role in allowing successful coordination, there is also a place for consciously designed institutions in overcoming the natural limits of sympathy. Hargreaves Heap, for his part, stresses the necessity of deriving prescriptive consequences from the expressive

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    18 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us