Introduction

Introduction

Introduction Natural Philosophy consists in discovering the frame and operations of Nature, and reducing them, as far as may be, to general Rules or Laws – establishing these rules by observations and experiments, and thence deducing the causes and effects of things. – Isaac Newton Newton as natural philosopher Newton’s scientific influence permeates our culture. Forces are measured in newtons, we have “Newton’s rings” and Newtonian fluids, we apply Newtonian mechanics in a remarkably wide range of cases, and the law of universal gravitation characterizes what is still considered to be a fun- damental force. Indeed, the very idea that a force can be “fundamental,” irreducible to any other force or phenomenon in nature, is largely due to Newton, and still has currency in the twenty-first century. Because of these achievements, Newton is regularly mentioned in the same breath with Copernicus and Galileo as a founder of modern science. Although Newton is rarely listed along with figures like Descartes or Spinoza as a founder of modern philosophy, and although he never wrote a treatise of the order of the Meditations or the Ethics, his influence on philosophy in Quoted by Richard Westfall, Never at Rest (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ), . This passage from Newton’s “Scheme for establishing the Royal Society” represents a contribution to the debate between naturalists and mathematically minded philosophers in the Royal Society before Newton ascended to its Presidency. For a discussion, see Mordechai Feingold, “Mathe- maticians and Naturalists,” in Jed Buchwald and I. Bernard Cohen (eds.), Isaac Newton’s Natural Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, ). ix Introduction the early modern period was nevertheless profound. Indeed, Newton was oneofthe great practitioners of what the early moderns called “natural philosophy.” Fully understanding Newton means avoiding anachronistically sub- stituting our conception of philosophy in the twenty-first century for what the early moderns understood by “natural philosophy.” To be sure, the latter includes much that we now call “science,” and yet it includes much else besides. Just as Newton painstakingly derived proposition after proposition concerning (say) the motion of bodies under certain condi- tions, he painstakingly went through draft after draft of his thoughts about (e.g.) the metaphysical status of space and time and God’s relation to the “system of the world.” This remains true despite the fact that his work on the former bequeathed to us a conception of science in which discus- sions of the latter play little if any role. Interpreting Newton solely as a “scientist” whose work spawned discussion by canonical philosophical figures ignores his contributions to the philosophical conversation in Eng- land and the Continent in his day.Newton was troubled by,and addressed, arange of issues that he considered to be philosophical in nature. These issues include the extent and underpinnings of our knowledge in physics; the ontological status of space and time; the relation between metaphys- ical and religious commitments on the one hand and empirical science on the other; and the proper characterization of God’s creation of – and place within – the universe. Thinking of Newton as a natural philosopher can also illuminate his intellectual influence on eighteenth-century philosophy,an influence that can hardly be overestimated and that spans the entire century, both in England and the Continent. The influence has at least two salient aspects. Newton’s achievement in the Opticks and in the Principia was understood to be of such philosophical import that few philosophers in the eighteenth century remained silent on it. Most of the canonical philosophers in this period sought to interpret various of Newton’s epistemic claims within the terms of their own systems, and many saw the coherence of their own views with those of Newton as a criterion of philosophical excellence. See Howard Stein, “Newton’s Metaphysics,” and Alan Gabbey, “Newton, Active Powers, and the Mechanical Philosophy,” chs. and , respectively, in I. Bernard Cohen and George Smith (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Newton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ), and Ernan McMullin, “The Impact of Newton’s Principia on the Philosophy of Science,” Philosophy of Science (). x Introduction Early in the century, Berkeley grappled with Newton’s work on the cal- culus in The Analyst and with his dynamics in De Motu, and he even discussed gravity, the paradigmatic Newtonian force, in his popular work Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous (). When Berkeley lists what philosophers take to be the so-called primary qualities of material bodies in the Dialogues,heremarkably adds “gravity” to the more familiar listofsize,shape,motion,andsolidity,therebysuggestingthatthereceived view of material bodies had already changed before the second edition of the Principia had circulated widely.Hume interpreted Newtonian natural philosophy in an empiricist vein and noted some of its broader implica- tions in his Treatise of Human Nature () and Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (). On the Continent, Kant attempted to forge a philosophically robust meditation between Leibnizian metaphysics and Newtonian natural philosophy, discussing Newtonian science at length in his Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (). Newton’s work also served as the impetus for the extremely influential correspondence between Leibniz and the Newtonian Samuel Clarke early in the century, a correspondence that proved significant even for thinkers writing toward the century’s end. Unlike the vis viva controversy and other disputes between the Cartesians and the Leibnizians, which died out by the middle of the century, the debate between the Leibnizians and the Newtonians remained philosophically salient for decades, serving as the backdrop to Kant’s treatment of space and time in the Critique of Pure Reason in .Newton’s work also spawned an immense commentarial literature in English, French, and Latin, including John Keill’s Intro- duction to Natural Philosophy (), Henry Pemberton’s AView of Sir Isaac Newton’s Philosophy (), Voltaire’s Elements of the Philosophy of Newton (), Emelie Du Chatelet’sˆ Institutions of Physics (), Willem s’Gravesande’s Mathematical Elements of Natural Philosophy (), and Colin MacLaurin’s An Account of Sir Isaac Newton’s Philosophical Discov- eries (). These and other commentaries were printed in various edi- tions, were translated into various languages, and were often influential. A second aspect of Newton’s influence involves thinkers who attempted in one way or another to follow the Newtonian “method” in natural philos- ophy when treating issues and questions that Newton ignored. Euclidean geometry and its methods were seen as a fundamental epistemic model formuch of seventeenth-century philosophy – Descartes’ Meditations attempts to achieve a type of certainty he likens to that found in geometry, xi Introduction and Spinoza wrote his Ethics according to the “geometrical method.” Propositions deduced from theorems in Euclidean geometry were seen as paradigm cases of knowledge. We might see Newton’s work as providing eighteenth-century philosophy with one of its primary models, and with a series of epistemic exemplars as well. David Hume is perhaps clearest about this aspect of Newton’s influence. His Treatise of has the sub- title: “An Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Method of Reasoning Into Moral Subjects,” and there can be no doubt that he meant the method of the Opticks and the Principia. Indeed, as Hume’s text makes abundantly clear, various eighteenth-century philosophers, including not only Hume in Scotland but Jean-Jacques Rousseau on the Continent, were taken to be, or attempted to become, “the Newton of the mind.” For Hume, this meant following what he took to be Newton’s empirical method by pro- viding the proper description of the relevant natural phenomena and then finding the most general principles that account for them. This method would allow us to achieve the highest level of knowledge attainable in the realm of what Hume calls “matters of fact.” Despite the influence of Newton’s “method” on eighteenth-century philosophy, it is obvious that the Principia’s greater impact on the eigh- teenth century is to have effected a separation between technical physics on the one hand, and philosophy on the other. In the hands of figures like Laplace and Lagrange, Newton’s work led to the progressive develop- ment of Newtonian mechanics, which remained the canonical expression of our understanding of many natural phenomena long after Newton’s influence in philosophy proper had ceased to be felt. And yet to achieve an understanding of how Newton himself understood natural philos- ophy, we must carefully bracket such historical developments. To cite Kuhn’s understanding of the development of a science, although Newton provided physics with its paradigm, he himself worked largely within its pre-paradigmatic context, and the pre-paradigmatic state, according to Kuhn, is typically characterized by extensive epistemological debates and controversies over the “foundations” or “first principles” of the science. Newton himself engages in precisely these discussions both in A proposition expressing a matter of fact cannot be known to be true without appeal to experience because,unlikeinthecaseof“relationsofideas,”thenegationofthepropositionisnotcontradictory. This distinction lives on, somewhat altered, in Kant’s distinction between analytic

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    31 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us