M. Schroder, Analogues of the Compact-Open Topology, P 83

M. Schroder, Analogues of the Compact-Open Topology, P 83

ANALOGUES OF THE COMPACT-OPEN TOPOLOGY M. Schroder (received 1 December, 1978; revised 10 December, 1979) Introduction For any collection L of subsets of a set X and any uniform space Y (indeed, for any uniform convergence space), the function space Y^ can be equipped with uniform L-convergence. It can also be given the L-open topology (when Y is topological), a topology shown to involve nothing more than the convergence of filters to sets. This idea enables one to define an L-convergence on Y^ for any convergence space Y at all, and then to recapture the L-open topology as a special case. Now suppose that X is a topological space and that C is a collection of continuous functions from X to Y . Classically, one finds (i) that if X is compactly generated and Y is topological, then the compact-open topology coincides on C with continuous convergence, (ii) that if X is locally compact and Y is a uniform space then continuous convergence and the topology of compact convergence coincide on C , and (iii) that compact convergence and the compact-open topology coincide on C when Y is a uniform space. More generally, let C consist of all f in Y^ , such that the same filters converge to f under both L-convergence and uniform L-convergence. Then X becomes a compactly generated space, and (a) each member of L is compact, (b) C is the set of all continuous functions from X to Y , and (c) L-convergence, uniform L-convergence and continuous convergence all coincide on C , provided that L and Y satisfy certain mild restrictions. This extension and partial converse Math. Chronicle 10(1981) 83-98. 83 of (iii) above is matched by similar improvements to (i) and (ii): the main problem left is - how much can the restriction be relaxed? Background Except for the basic calculus of filters, most tools used later are briefly introduced in this section: fuller treatment can be found in the works cited, results being stated mainly without proof. 1. Sets and filters. For any set Q , let Pow(Q) and Fil(Q) stand for the power set of Q and the set of all filters on Q . As usual, if A c Q and x € Q then A and x are the principal filters based on {i4} and {{as}} respectively. In particular, 0 = Pow(Q) is regarded as a filter, known as the improper filter. All other filters are proper. If M and N are collections of subsets of Q , one says that M meets W if M fl N is non-void. Every function h : Pow(P) — *■ Fil{Q) such that li(A U fl) = h(A) fl h(B) for all A , B in Pow(P) , can be 'extended' to a fl-homomorphism from Fil{P) to Fil(Q) as follows: if A is a filter on P , then h(A) is defined to be the filter U{h(i4) : A € A}. Lemma 1. Under these conditions, an ultrafilter on Q finer than h(K) is finer than h(U) for some ultra filter U finer than A . With each non-void collection r of filters on Q are associated its segmental, Choquet and principal modifications, denoted by oT , oT and nr respectively. A filter belongs (i) to oT as soon as it is finer than some member of r , (ii) to oF provided that every finer ultrafilter belongs to oT , and (iii) to nT if it is finer than the fi Iter nr = [A : A € A for all A f f). 84 Naturally r is said to be a segment if r = oT , Choquet if T = oT and principal if T = ttT . (There is another procedure known as solidification [8] which also leads to oT : so r may be called solid instead of Choquet if F = oT .) 2. Point and set convergence. One method of formalising the idea of convergence uses a function, associating with each point, the collection of filters which 'converge' to that point. Thus a (point) convergence y on Q is defined to be a function y from Q to Pou(Fil(Q) ) . Though other more (or less) restrictive definitions have been given elsewhere (see [5] or [6]), it is assumed here that for all x in Q , (^p) y(®) is a segment, and (Cj) x belongs to y(x) . Similarly, a set convergence on Q is a function from Pow(Q) to Pow(Fil(Q)) such that for all A , B in Pow(Q) and all filters F , G and H on Q , (SQ) r(4) is a segment, (Sj) A belongs to r(>4) , and (S2) if W is finer than F O G and F € r(>i) and G €r(B) then H £ r(4 U B). One often uses more descriptive terms such as "F — ►A under F", "x is a Y-limit of G " or the like, instead of "F € r(/l)" and "G £ y(*)" • Each set convergence T on Q defines a convergence F* by 'restriction' : F — *■x under r* iff F —> {x} under r . On the other hand, each convergence y can be 'extended' to a set convergence 85 y# as follows: F —A >- under y* iff ^ is finer than the filter fl{F : x £ A] , for some choice of the filters F in y(x) • x x However, not every set convergence arises in this way. For example, take an infinite set P , define y(x) = {$,x,U^} where the ^'s are distinct non-trivial ultrafilters, and put F in r(i4) if F — ►A under y* , but in the notation used above, F = x for all bar finitely x many x in A . In all cases though, y = y** and T is finer than r** (that is, T-convergence implies r**-convergence). Further, r = y* for some convergence y iff r = r** . Applying the operators o and it pointwise to the convergence y » one obtains its Choquet modification ay and its principal modification ny . Similarly one calls yChoquet or principal when the segments y(x) are all Choquet or principal. Analogous terminology is also used for set convergences. Finally, a subset U of Q is called y-open if U belongs to every filter y-converging to some point of U . The set of all y-open subsets of Q is a topology, which generates a convergence xy coarser than y . Thus one calls y topological if y = xy . More information about topological convergence can be found in [5] and [7] along with references to some of the original work. Note though the following facts. Lemma 2. (i) The convergence y is principal iff yA is principal. (ii) If U is y-open and F converges to a subset of U under y* then U belongs to F . (iii) In particular, if y is topological then the y-neighbourhood filter of a set is the coarsest filter y A-converging to that set. 86 3. Uniform convergence structures. Again let e be a set, Q2 = Q * Q and Dq the diagonal in Q2 . C.ll. Cook and H.R. Fischer [3] called a collection ft of filters on Q2 a uniform convergence structure if (f/Q) ft is a segment, (U.) D belongs to ft , 1 y (U^) F O G belongs to ft if both F and G do, (#3) ft is symmetric, meaning that it is closed under converses, and (i/^) ft is closed under composition of relations. More generally, one calls ft a uniform rule if UQ to U 3 all hold: the yet weaker axioms used by some other authors would cause minor inconvenience later. The convergence w derived from a uniform rule ft by defining "F converges to x under a)” if F * x belongs to ft , is symmetric, in that y — *-x under w exactly when uj({/) = w(a:) . The properties U^ are all stable under Choquet modification, meaning that if ft satisfies U^ then so does oft . Furthermore, if ft is a uniform rule, the convergence derived from oft coincides with od) , and in particular, w is Choquet whenever ft is a Choquet uniform rule. 4. Compactness and regularity. Let y be a convergence on Q . A subset K of Q is said to be compact (or more precisely, y-compact) if every ultra-filter on Q to which K belongs y-converges to some point of K , and y itself is called compact if Q is y-compact. Only a rather weak regularity axiom is needed here: y is called R j i if no proper filter both y-converges to x and rry-converges to y, 87 unless y — *■ x under y • (In [8], a slightly stronger axiom,R^ was needed to prove that any compact symmetric R^ ^ Choquet convergence was topological, and hence regular. Similarly, one can show that any compact symmetric R^ j Choquet convergence is principal: the existence of compact Hausdorff principal convergences which are not topological shows that R^ ^ is strictly weaker than R^ ^ .) 5. Multiplication and covers. Let y and 6 be convergences on Q . One constructs convergences y*6 and y*6 by demanding (W*) F — x under y*S iff filters G in 6(x) and R in y(j/) for all y in Q can be U so chosen that F is finer than fl{R : y $ G) , y for all G in G , and (M-:) F — +x under y*6 iff there is a filter G in 6 (as) such that F — ►G under y* for all G in G . Clearly y*6 is finer than y*6 and equally clearly, they coincide if y is principal.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    16 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us