Stichting Mathematisch Centrum· 2E Boerhaavestraat 49 Amsterdam

Stichting Mathematisch Centrum· 2E Boerhaavestraat 49 Amsterdam

zw stichting mathematisch ~ centrum· MC AFDELING ZUIVERE WISKUNDE zw 44/75 JUNE T .M. V. JANSSEN tN ARITHMETIZATION OF VAN WIJNGAARDEN GRAMMAR 7 L 2e boerhaavestraat 49 amsterdam Bl81.10l'~fi!il:{, MATHtMATISCH Cl'Nll/\•i.',li, PJu..n.:ted a..t the Ma..thema.:Uc..a.l Cen:tlie, 49, 2e BoeJihaave1:i.:tJr.aa.t, Am.o.teJidam. The Ma..thema:tic..a.l Cen:tlie, 6ou.n.ded .the 11-.th 06 FebJr..uafl_Y 1946, -loan.on.­ p1r..06U in..o.tltu.tlon. curn,ln.g a..t .the ph..omotion. 06 pUll.e ma..thema.:UCA an.d w app..Uc.a.:Uon..6. I.t -lo .opon..ooJr..ed by .the Nethe.Jilan.d6 GoveJin.men.:t .thh..ough the Nethe.Jilan.d6 01r..gan.,Lza.:Uon. 6oJr.. .the Advanc.emen.:t 06 PWl.e Re1:,ea1r..c.h (Z.W.O), by .the Mun.,Lupa..uty 06 Am.oteJidam, by .the Un.,lveMUy 06 Am.oteJidam, by the F1r..ee UniveMUy a..t Am.oteJidam, an.d by indU.6.:tluel:i. AMS(MOS) subject classification scheme (1970): 68A30, 02F43, 02F99 An Arithmetization of van Wijngaarden Grammar by T.M.V. Janssen ABSTRACT An arithmetization is given of the concept of a van Wijngaarden grannnar, by means of which it is proved that each van Wijngaarden grammar generates a recursively enumerable language. KEYWORDS & PHRASES: van Wijngaarden grarronar, arithmetization, generative aapaaity, reaursively enwnerable languages. INTRODUCTION Every recursively enumerable language can be generated by a van Wijngaarden grammar. This has been proved by SINTZOFF [9]; an elegant proof has been given by VAN WIJNGAARDEN [12] who showed that only one metanotion is needed to do so. The present report contains a formal proof of the reverse that each van Wijngaarden grammar generates a recursively enumerable language; no such proof has yet been given, as this fact is belied to be obvious by Church's thesis. The method of our proof is sketched as follows. A van Wijngaarden grammar concerns strings of symbols; it generates strings of special symbols and it gives rise to relations between strings (such as string s 1 can be obtained from string s 2 by applying some rule of the grammar). The problem we consider, is the question whether a set of special strings is recursively enumerable. We shall, however, not directly deal with this problem, but rather with a translation of it. We use a 1-1 encoding of strings of symbols in numbers. Relations between strings, become relations between numbers, and the problem becomes the question whether a set of special numbers is recursively enumerable. By solving the translated problem we have indirectly solved the original problem since the encoding is 1-1. This method, which is called arithmetization, is well known in recursion theory. We actually will obtain the result by defining a predicate wordgener­ ation (X,w,d), where Xis the code number of a van Wijngaarden grammar, w is the code number of a string and d encodes all the information about the derivation of w. From the definition of this predicate it will become clear that this predicate is primitive recursive. Apparently w E L(X) iff 3d[wordgeneration(X,w,d)], thus L(X) is recursively enumerable. The predi­ cate wordgeneration can actually be shown to be elementary recursive; this shows that the arithmetization is of the same complexity as the well known arithmetizations of Turing machines and of Markov algorithms. 2 FROM FORMAL LANGUAGE THEORY We recall the following from formal language theory; for details see HOPCROFT & ULLMAN [6]. Let V be a finite set. Then V+ is the set of all non empty strings consisting of elements from V, thus V+ = {v1···vn n ~ I, v. EV}. We indicate the empty string with A and put v* = V+ u {A}. 1. For w Ev*, let lwl denote the length of w. We designate a Chomsky grammar ( shortly grammar) by G = (V, E, P, S) where V is a finite set, E c V, SE V-E and Pc V+xv* is a finite set: the rules or productions. If there are no restrictions on P, then G is of Chomsky type O or shortly type-O. If Jul s lvl for each (u,v) E P then G is context-sensitive. If u E V-E for each (u,v) E P then G is context-free. If (u,v) E P and x,y Ev* then xuy Gxvy. We denote by i the transitive, reflexive closure of G" We omit subscripts G when no confusion is likely. The language gener­ ated by G is L(G) = {w Er* I S ! w}. A A-rule is a rule (u,v) E P with v = A. A homomorphism his a mapping v* • w*, where V and Ware finite sets, and h(xy) = h(x)h(y) for all x,y EV.* FROM RECURSION THEORY We recall the following facts from recursion theory; for details and proofs see DAVIS [3]. (I) The operation composition associates with the functions Ay 1 ••. ym f(y 1, ... ,ym), Ax 1 ••• xn g(x1, ••• ,xn), ••• , Ax 1 ... xn g(x1, •.• ,xn) the function (2) The operation of primitive recursion associates with the given total functions Ax 1 ••. xn f(x 1, ••• ,xn) and Azyx 1 ••• xn g(z,y,x1, ••• ,xn) the function Azx ••• x h(z,x , ••• ,x) where for all z,x , ••• ,x the 1 n 1 n I n following holds: 3 h(O,x1, ••• ,xn) = f(x1, ••• ,xn) , h(z+t,x1, ••• ,xn) = g(z,h(z,x1, ••• ,xn),x1, ••• ,xn). (3) A function is called a primitive reau:t'sive function if it can be obtained by a finite number of applications of the operations of composition and primitive recursion, beginning with functions from the following list: (i) >..x(x+l), (ii) >..x(O), (iii) >..x ••• x (x.). 1 n 1 (4) The following functions are primitive recursive >..xy(x+y) >..xy(xy) (5) Ann-place predicate Pis called a primitive recursive predicate if the characteristic function of the set {(x1, ••• ,xn) I P(x1, ••• ,xn)} is primitive recursive. (6) If P and Qare primitive recursive predicates, then so are the conjunc­ tion PA Q, the disjunction P v Q, the implication P • Q and the negated predicate 7 P. (7) The predicates<,~,>,~,=,* are primitive recursive. (8) If P(y,x1 , ••• ,xn) is a primitive recursive predicate, then the predicates R(zl ,zz,Xl ' ••• ,xn), meaning 3y[(z1 ~ y :;_ z2 A P(y,x1, ••• ,xn)J and S(z1 ,z2,x1 , ••• ,xn), meaning Vy[(z 1 ~ y ~ z2 • P(y,x1, ••• ,xn)J are again primitive recursive. The usual notation for these two predicates are Zz 3y P(y,x , ••• ,xn) zl 1 and z2 '/Y P(y,xt,···,xn) 1 respectively. 4 (9) We use the ~allowing definition of recursively enumerable set (this definition is equivalent to the one given by DAVIS [3]): A set Sis called recUPsiveZy enumerabZe if there exists a primitive recursive predicate P(x,y) such that S = {x I 3y P(x,y)}. CODING In the sequel we encode sequences of natural numbers in natural numbers; therefore, we need a primitive recursive function from nQO lNn to 1N. For convenience we require this function to be onto. The value of the function for the sequence x 1, .•• ,xn is denoted by tx1, .•. ,xn*· The value for the empty sequence is denoted by f *· We require this function to have the property that for all I$ i $ j $ n holds: f x. , ... , x . * $ t x , ... , x. , ..• , x . , ... , x * . l. J 1 i J n We require the following functions and predicate to be primitive recursive: the function L , which gives the length of an encoded sequence; thus L(fx1, •.. ,xn*) = n; the function( •• )., which gives the i-th element of a sequence; thus l. (tx , ••. ,x *>· = x. for I $ i $ n; 1 n l. l. the function* , which gives the code number of the concatenation of two sequences; thus X*Y = Hx)1,···,<x\(x),<Y)1,····(y\cy)*; the predicate EZem, where EZem(X,x) holds if£ for some i the i-th element in the sequence encoded by X, equals x. We define the primitive recursive function AXY • it(x,y) by { it(x,0) = t * it(x,n+I) = it(x,n) * Ox*). The primitive recursive function AX It(x) is now defined by It(x) = it(x,L(x)). The function It has the following useful! property. Let a= ta1, ..• ,an*' b = {b , ..• , b *• where m $ n, and let b , , •• and b be equal to subsequences of 1 m I m a , ... ,a (with b. = t * for at most one i). Then b $ It(a). We will use 1 n l. this estimate to bound quantifications. 5 There are several codings which have the desired properties and for which the required functions and predicate are primitive recursive. For example, see TROELSTRA [10] (proofs concerning the properties of this code are found in §:Z of KREISEL & TROELSTRA [7]) or VAN WIJNGAARDEN [13]. Tl1e actual choice of this code is, for our aims, arbitrarily. Even the use of an onto coding is not essential (for a code which is not onto see DAVIS [3]), but then one needs a primitive recursive predicate which tells whether a number is the code number of a sequence, and the definitions of the func­ tions and predicate have to be adjusted in order to remain total. DEFINITIONS CONCERNING VAN WIJNGAARDEN GRAMMARS A van Wijngaarden grammar (W-grammar) is an ordered sixtuple G = (VM,IT,L,PM,PH,S) where the following holds: VM is a finite set, the elements of which are called metavariahles; L is a finite set, the elements of which are called terminal symbols or terminals; IT is a finite set, the elements of which are called protovariables; S is a special symbol in IT, called the start symbol.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    18 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us