ON the LOGARITHMS of NEGATIVE and IMAGINARY NUMBERS Leonhard Euler

ON the LOGARITHMS of NEGATIVE and IMAGINARY NUMBERS Leonhard Euler

ON THE LOGARITHMS OF NEGATIVE AND IMAGINARY NUMBERS Leonhard Euler 1. In the exchange of letters between Messrs. Leibnitz and Jean Bernoulli, we find a great controversy over the logarithms of negative and imaginary numbers, a controversy which has been treated by both sides with much force, without however, these two illustrious men having fallen into agreement on this matter, although otherwise we note a very perfect harmony between them on all the other points of analysis. This dissension seems all the more remarkable because it centers upon an article of the part of mathematics which we call pure, and which we do not ordinarily believe susceptible to any dispute, it all being based on the most rigorous proofs. For we know that the other questions on which mathematicians are not in agreement belong to the applied part of mathematics, where the diverse ways of envisaging the objects and reducing them to mathematical ideas give rise to real controversies; and we even boast that they have been altogether banished from analysis or pure mathematics. 2. Indeed, the glory of infallibility which this science has acquired would suffer a great attack, if there were questions on which beliefs were not only divided, but where it were even impossible to discover the truth by a clear proof which would put an end to all dispute. Since there is not the slightest doubt that such an accommodation between the differing opinions of Messrs. Leibnitz and Bernoulli has not taken place, I will examine both, weighing the argu- ments which each invokes both for the confirmation of his belief as well as for the refutation of the contrary, and I hope to develop this matter well and put it into full light, so that there will not remain the slightest doubt and so that both parties will be obliged to recognize the solidness of the verdict I will give, and which will put an end to all the disputes which might yet arise on this matter. Sur les logarithmes des nombres negatifs et imaginaires. Actor. Acad. Berolinensis tomo V. A. 1749 p. 139 Number 807 in the Enestr¨omindex. Translation Copyright °c 2005 Todd Doucet. All Rights Reserved. Comments & queries: [email protected] 2 ON THE LOGARITHMS OF 3. M. Leibnitz gave the first occasion to this controversy with M. Bernoulli, when he advanced in letter CXC that the ratio of 1 to −1, or of −1 to 1, was imaginary, since the logarithm or measure of this ratio is imaginary, where he clearly was assuming that the logarithms of negative numbers are imaginary or impossible. To this M. Bernoulli declared, in letter CXCIII, that he was not of the same opinion and that he even believed the logarithms of negative numbers were not only real, but also equal to the logarithms of the same numbers taken positively. He holds, then, that `(+x) = `(−x), which he claims to prove by the equality of their differentials, considering that dx d ` x = x and furthermore −dx dx d `(−x) = = . −x x Against this argument M. Leibnitz responds that the common rule of differen- tiating logarithms, by dividing the differential of the number by the number itself, is appropriate only for positive numbers and that, consequently, this dx differentiation d ` x = x is appropriate only when x indicates a positive quantity. But I admit that this response, if it were right, would shake the foundation of all of analysis, which consists principally in the generality of the rules and operations which are judged to be true, whatever the nature we suppose the quantities to be that we apply them to. 4. But, even though the rule to differentiate logarithms is generally true, so dx that d ` x = x whether x is a positive or negative quantity, the argument of M. Bernoulli does not prove what it claims to prove. I say that just because the differentials of the quantities `(x) and `(−x) are equal, it does not at all follow that the quantities themselves are equal to each other, because we know that two quantities which differ by a constant have the same differential. Thus the differentials of x + 1 and of x − 1 are both equal to dx, without us being able to conclude an equality between the quantities x + 1 and x − 1. Besides that, M. Bernoulli could have proved by the same reasoning that ` 2x = ` x, since 2 dx dx d ` 2x = = = d ` x 2x x NEGATIVE AND IMAGINARY NUMBERS 3 and in general it would follow that `(nx) = `(x), where n indicates an arbi- trary number. That is why from the equality between the differentials of `(x) and `(−x), we cannot conclude anything, except that these two logarithms differ by a constant quantity. And indeed, `(−x), because −x = x · (−1), is none other than `(x) + `(−1). It is true that M. Bernoulli claimed that `(−1) = `(1) = 0, in which case we would without doubt have `(−x) = `(+x), but this is precisely what M. Leibnitz had denied and M. Bernoulli wished to prove by this argument, so that in this area, nothing is yet decided. 5. In the same passage which I just examined, M. Bernoulli makes use of still another argument, but one which differs from the preceding only in the way it is said, when he holds that the logarithmic curve has, from two sides of its asymptote, two equal and similar parts, so that to each abscissa or logarithm there correspond two ordinates or equal numbers, one positive and the other negative. For, considering the equation of this curve y dx = a dy, where x indicates the abscissa taken on the asymptote of the logarithm, y the ordinate, and a the constant subtangent, it would seem to follow that, if to the same abscissa x there corresponds the value y = u, it will correspond also to y = −u, since, if +u dx = +a du, we will also have −u dx = −a du. But this reasoning is similar to the preceding, and it would follow from it as well that to each abscissa x, there would also correspond the ordinate y = 2u, and in general y = nu, so that this curve would have not only two ordinates, y = u and y = −u, which would correspond to the abscissa x, but the number of ordinates would be infinite. This is a consequence, however, that we are quite a long way from admitting. From this we see that this argument does not prove that the logarithm has two similar branches on two sides of its asymptote. 6. But one will perhaps object that it is nevertheless the surest means to judge the shape of a curve and the number of its branches by its equation, and that it is by this principle that the geometers determine the forms of all the algebraic curves. To which I respond that this method has a place only when the equation for the curve is algebraic or at least conceived in finite terms, and that a differential equation is never appropriate to this design. For we know that a differential equation is always indeterminate, because of an arbitrary constant it includes which we must introduce in the integration, 4 ON THE LOGARITHMS OF so that such an equation always embraces an infinity of curves at the same time. We only have to look at the differential equation for the parabola 2y dy = a dx, and we will see that it contains not only this finite equation y2 = ax, but also this one y2 = ax ± ab, whatever value we give to the quantity b. Consequently, by considering only the differential equation 2y dy = a dx, we would have to conclude that to the √ same√ abscissa x there corresponds not√ only the ordinate y = ax, but again y = ax ± a2, and in general y = ax ± ab. This reflection is sufficient to show that we cannot judge the shape of a curve by looking at only its differential equation. 7. Now, M. Bernoulli, as well as several mathematicians who also hold the same belief, try to prove by still other arguments that the asymptote of the logarithm is at the same time its diameter. These arguments are based either on the construction of this curve, or else on analogy. One makes use of dy analogy by considering, instead of the equation for the logarithmic dx = y , this more general one dy dx = yn whose integral is 1 x = C − . (n − 1)yn−1 We note here that whenever n is an odd number, the curve has, without question, a diameter, or two equal and similar branches. This noted, the argument is that we suppose n = 1, and since 1 is an odd number, the log- arithmic must have the same property. This is, in my opinion, the strongest argument that we have heretofore brought for proving that the logarithmic has a diameter. But I will nevertheless show that this conclusion we want to draw is not sufficiently certain. 8. When it is a question, in analysis, of the case of integrability or, in ge- ometry, of certain properties of curves, we rarely find propositions that are general enough, and it is nearly always necessary to except one or several NEGATIVE AND IMAGINARY NUMBERS 5 cases which do not apply. One can indeed say that this formula xndx is in general integrable, whatever number we put for n, provided that we exclude the case n = −1. And it is the same as well with several other general for- mulas, which we can almost never affirm are integrable in all cases without exception.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    19 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us