Mathematical Logic: Mathematics of Logic Or Logic of Mathematics Z

Mathematical Logic: Mathematics of Logic Or Logic of Mathematics Z

MATHEMATICAL LOGIC: MATHEMATICS OF LOGIC OR LOGIC OF MATHEMATICS Z. Šikić This brief historical survey, written from the logical point of view, is a rational reconstruction of the genesis of some interrelations between formal logic and mathematics. We start with the period which preceded the important logical writings of Boole. At the end of the first half of 19th century formal logic was being developed mainly in Great Britain, under the influence of the newly raising abstract algebra, which have just begun to appear in the papers of G. Peacock, J. Gregory, A. de Morgan and W. R. Hamilton. Attempts to apply mathematical analysis (which proved so fruitful and convincing in studying the laws of Quality) to formal logic (which deals with the laws of Quality) became characteristic for that period. Setting a suitable symbolic apparatus and founding the laws of its manipulation, in the same way arithmetic does it, was the ultimate purpose of the use of the new method. Similar attempts originated from earlier periods and other places (e. g. G. W. Leibniz on continent) but the first great success was achieved in 1847 by Boole’s “Mathematical Analysis of Logic”. It was Boole who showed that the fundamental operations with concepts (operations of thought, he would say) can be represented by arithmetic operations, addition, subtraction and multiplication; while the fundamental concepts of Everything and Nothing can be represented by 1 and 0. Namely, these operations are governed by the arithmetic laws (i. e. by the laws of operations with quantities) together with an additional one: x2 = x (called the principle of tautology) characteristic and distinctive for operations with qualities. Thus the logic of concepts (or classes) became special arithmetic and it is in this way that G. Boole understands it. What is a conclusion? Premises are equations which, using arithmetic operations, can produce other equations, the latter being thus conclusions of the arithmetized reasoning. The problem of the logical interpretation of the obtained equations is solved by reducing the equation to its normal form, applying Taylor’s formula characteristic for this (x2 = x)-arithmetic: f(x) = f(1)x – f(0)(1 – x). By this analysis the logic of concepts acquired simplicity, safety and generality of arithmetic. In other words, it was well, and that meant arithmetically, founded. Equations which was not possible to interpret in the course of the proof were a disturbance to the purely logical understanding of the basic laws, and hence there began de- arithmetizing of formal logic (i. e. G. Boole himself, W. S. Jevons, S. C. Pierce, J. Venn, E. Schröder)1). The final result was a Boole-Schroeder algebra which represented, in its various interpretations, the logic of concepts, the logic of one-place propositional functions (from G. Boole on), as well as the logic of propositions (from C. S. Pierce and E. Schröder on). It should be noted that terms propositional function and proposition bring along views and contents which have not been treated yet in this period (see 2)). Bearing in mind the period we have been trying to analyse it is better to say that the logic of primary and secondary propositions or categorical and hypothetical syllogisms in particular, obey the same Boole- Schröder’s laws. De-arithmetizing of formal logic has not basically changed the character of its founding (which is often thought and said on the basis of the later logistic or formalistic understanding of the reduction of mathematics) but it has substantially influenced the character of mathematics. Namely, Boole-Schröder’s algebra has been founded as an abstract mathematical system, independent of its particular interpretation, by the method of deduction from a small number of premises, the method which in itself becomes a characteristic of mathematics regardless of the quantitative or any other character of the matter being researched. However, the method itself becomes a paradox if the system, which is being founded, is formal logic itself: mathematical deductions are unavoidably based on the laws which are yet to be founded in formal logic. Consequently, the result of purifying formal logic by de-arithmetizing it, was not a pure formal logic, but rather a pure mathematics. In this sense, G. Boole is the father of pure mathematics and impure mathematical logic2). This discussion bring us to the new epoch in the development of formal logic and mathematics, and hereby we end the survey of the epoch which originally considers formal logic as a special arithmetic, then as a special case of pure mathematics and which accordingly introduces the term mathematical analysis of logic, reminiscent of the term mathematical logic, if we read it as mathematics of logic. The criticism of the infinitesimal calculus and the return of mathematics to the problem of its foundation in 1850-s, clearly stated the need for the foundation of the arithmetic of real numbers. It is a period of the critical movement in mathematics, a period when K. Weirstrass became a supreme mathematical authority (“Notre maître à tous”, said Hermite), a period where the intuition of space and time is being rejected, by informal logical analysis, as a basis of arithmetic. In this period R. Dedekind arithmetizes the continuum of real numbers3) and further sets a problem of natural number genesis, saying: “When I say that arithmetic (algebra, analysis) is only a part of logic, I already state that I consider the concept of number completely independent of the notions or intuitions of space and time, and, on the contrary, I consider it to be a direct product of the pure laws of reasoning”4). It is the beginning of the epoch which does not have a good ear for the logic which looks for support in arithmetic, but on the contrary, it looks for support of arithmetic (and mathematics) in logic. However, this radical turning point was gradually prepared by adopting and developing one more aspect of the critical movement in mathematics. In the mind of the leading mathematicians at the end of 19th century, there is a clear-cut ideal of a mathematical theory which is derived from the small number of (mathematical) premises in accordance with the logical principles; the ideal of the theory which rejects intuition even as a means of demonstration. Some more radical thinkers like G. Peano realized that the deductive science understood in this way (which demands postulation and definition of its basic entities5) but also a radical cleansing of the deductive process from the influence of intuition) can be formulated only within the frame of a symbolic language which is freed from the intuitive content of natural languages. Mathematics has already developed such a language to a great extent. However, G. Peano thinks that it is necessary (according to the new concept of the deductive science) to do something that has not been done even in mathematics: to formalize and symbolically describe the very arguments of mathematics. With this purpose in mind he designed mathematical logic and used it in the formalization of mathematics6). Due to this mathematical logic, the deduction of a conclusion from premises was replaced by formal generation of the respective symbolic expression, from other expressions of that kind, by a quasi-algebraic process7). Hence, mathematics was freed from intuition, becoming a set of propositions in the form of “p implies q”, where p represents a conjunction of the postulated mathematical assertions (axioms) and q their quasi-algebraically (mechanically) derived consequence8). The connection between this aspect of the critical movement with the one represented by Dedekind, who stated that the basic constituents of mathematical propositions (natural number, integer, rational number, real number) are logically definable9), draws attention to the possibility of p and q being purely logical propositions (propositions made up of purely logical concepts), i.e. that mathematics, freed from intuition, has become a set of purely logical propositions in the form of “p implies q”; in other words, that mathematics has become a part of logic. Joining these two aspects of the critical movement in mathematics and a consistent acceptance of such an attitude is to the merit of B. Russell10). In this way, a logicist epoch in the apprehension of the relations of formal logic and mathematics has been initiated, an epoch which considers arithmetic, and consequently all pure mathematics, as a part of logic and which accordingly introduces the term mathematical logic 11) reading it as logic of mathematics. 1) The title of W. S. Jevon’s paper is characteristic: Pure Logic or the Logic of Quality part from Quantity. 2) Yet, some “purification” of formal logic did take place. The various interpretations of Boole-Schröder’s algebra show (today?) that the logic of concepts and one-place propositional functions is founded by the logic of propositions. (Since this algebra eventually remained in the background of the logical researches and was not being frequently connected with the later logic of propositions and propositional functions, it is only recently that this important result is used to prove in a simple way the decidability of monadic logic in a student textbook (cf. [Q] ch.24).) 3) Cf. [D1] 4) Cf. [D2] 5) G. Peano has remarkably pointed to the trickiness of the intuitive comprehension of the basic mathematical entities, constructing a curve which fills a two-dimensional area, [P3]. 6) Cf. [P1] and [P2]. 7) It seems as if this procedure were not essentially different from Boole’s, doesn’t it? Yet, it is. Bolle’s logic is the applied pure mathematics and the former is based on the latter. Peano’s logic is the basis of pure mathematics and here the latter is based on the former.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    8 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us