Collective Memory

Collective Memory

11 Collective Memory Kourken Michaelian and John Sutton 1. COLLECTIVE MEMORY AND COLLECTIVE INTENTIONALITY Th ere has been relatively little interaction between research on collective intentionality in philosophy and research on collective memory in psychology and the social sciences. Rather than being due to a lack of mutual relevance—as this chapter will demonstrate, the two traditions are very much relevant to each other—this lack of interaction is due largely to somewhat arbitrary disciplinary barriers. But disciplinary barriers, even when arbitrary, have real consequences, and one message of this chapter is that the lack of inter- action has had negative consequences for both fi elds. Psychologists and social scientists have tended not to take advantage of philosophical resources that might sharpen their analyses of collective memory. Philosophers, meanwhile, have oft en presupposed overly simple models of the interactions among group members that are at work in the forma- tion of collective memories and collective intentional states more broadly. Th ere are thus important potential benefi ts to be realized for each fi eld through increased interaction with the other. Forms of Collective Memory What sorts of collectives are at issue in collective memory? Collective remembering unfolds at a range of scales, and it is necessary to be alert to the possibility of real diff er- ences between small-scale collective memory and large-scale collective memory. It may turn out that the same process of collective remembering unfolds in both small-scale and large-scale groups, but it may be no coincidence that small-scale and large-scale collec- tive memory have traditionally been investigated by diff erent disciplines. Th e former, exemplifi ed by remembering in married couples (Harris et al. 2014) or in parent-child dyads (Reese et al. 1993), has been studied primarily in psychology. Th e latter has been studied primarily in the social sciences and history. Indeed, refl ecting what has been 140 COLLECTIVE MEMORY 141 termed a “memory boom” (Blight 2009), an enormous amount of work on large-scale collective memory has appeared in recent years, building on older theories of remember- ing as a social process (Halbwachs 1994; see Wertsch 2009; Erll and Nünning 2010; Erll 2011; Olick et al. 2011). Th is disciplinary division of labor refl ects an apparent diff er- ence between the kinds of remembering of which small-scale and large-scale groups are, respectively, capable. In the standard taxonomy of kinds of memory (Michaelian, 2016), episodic memory refers to memory for experienced events. Episodic remembering is normally accompa- nied by a characteristic phenomenology, a sense of reliving the past (Tulving 1972). Semantic memory refers to memory for facts. Semantic remembering need not concern experienced events, and, when it does, it is not accompanied by a sense of reliving the past. Both episodic and semantic memory are declarative, in the sense that their contents can in principle be articulated; declarative memory aligns with what epistemologists refer to as “knowledge that.” Procedural memory, in contrast, is non-declarative and aligns with what epistemologists refer to as “knowledge how”; the contents of procedural memory—e.g. acquired skills of various sorts—need not be articulable. Memory in large-scale groups is typically memory for events which are of concern to the individuals who make up the group but in which those individuals did not necessarily take an active part and of which they oft en have only indirect knowledge. Extending the standard taxonomy to collective memory, large-scale collective memory thus appears oft en to be semantic. Consider the ways in which the citizens of a country might remem- ber key events from its past: individual citizens may (episodically) remember personal experiences which are linked to the events in question, but, to the extent that remember- ing is concerned with large-scale, public events, it lacks the characteristic features of episodic memory. Memory in small-scale groups—groups suffi ciently small to allow their members to interact directly with each other—can likewise be semantic. Research employing the collaborative recall paradigm, which compares the information recalled by groups of individuals who remember alone to that recalled by groups of individuals who interact with each other, for example, normally concerns learned information of no particular personal signifi cance (Weldon and Bellinger 1997). Small-scale collective memory can also sometimes be procedural. Research on transactive memory systems, for example, in some cases concerns group performance on a variety of practical tasks (Wegner 1987; Liang et al. 1995). Th e existence of procedural memory in small-scale groups may consti- tute an important diff erence between small-scale and large-scale collective memory, since there is no obvious sense in which large-scale groups are capable of remembering how to do something, but we will not pursue this here. Our focus, instead, will be on episodic memory. It appears that small-scale collective memory, unlike large-scale collective memory, may sometimes be episodic, in the sense that it is memory for events in which group members took an active part and hence of which they have direct knowledge. Stages of Collective Remembering What sorts of remembering are at issue in collective memory? In philosophy, remember- ing has sometimes been treated as a simple process in which a representation produced by a source other than memory is preserved over time. In psychology, in contrast, 142 KOURKEN MICHAELIAN AND JOHN SUTTON remembering is understood as a constructive, multi-stage process (Michaelian 2016). Th e initial stage of the process, leading from an experience to the production of a short- term memory representation, is encoding . Short-term representations are not mere copies of experience but result from processes of selection, abstraction, interpretation, and inte- gration with existing knowledge (Alba and Hasher 1983). Encoding therefore oft en amounts to the production of a new representation. Following encoding, a process of consolidation is responsible for transforming the labile, short-term representation into a stable, long-term representation, with the representation remaining labile—subject to fur- ther transformation—throughout the extended consolidation process. Consolidation thus likewise amounts to the production of a new representation. Only when consolidation is complete can the representation be said to have achieved stable storage . Moreover, retrieval , like encoding and consolidation, is a constructive process in which a stored representation is recombined with other relevant information to produce another new representation. Th e concepts of encoding, consolidation, storage, and retrieval are normally applied to remembering understood as an individual-level process, and the social dimension of remembering sometimes makes its appearance in the form of external factors aff ecting the accuracy of individual memory at the encoding, consolidation, or retrieval stages— oft en negatively, as in work on social contagion (Roediger et al. 2001) or the misinforma- tion eff ect (Loft us 2005). Applying the concepts to remembering understood as a group- level process, however, may provide a useful means of distinguishing among diff erent senses in which the memory process itself can be collective: rather than asking simply about “collective memory” in general, we can ask more precise questions about collective encoding, consolidation, storage, and retrieval. 2. ENCODING AND RETRIEVAL Some stages of a given process of remembering might be best understood as occurring at the individual level, while others are best understood as group-level processes, giving rise to a range of more or less strongly collective forms of memory. Refl ecting the emphases of the existing literature, we focus initially (in this section) on encoding and retrieval in small-scale collective memory and then (in Section 3) on consolidation and storage in large-scale collective memory. Th e wide range of views in the broader collective inten- tionality literature on what it takes for a phenomenon to be truly collective, and on the relations between individual and collective cognitive states and processes, will be refl ected in discussions of memory as philosophers come to integrate these fi elds together more thoroughly. Here we aim to home in on stronger views, on which it is the small group itself that can in certain circumstances remember. Memory in Small-Scale Groups Both encoding and retrieval in groups might be either parallel , in the sense that each group member implements the process without signifi cant interaction with the others, or interactive, in the sense that group members interact. Putting the interactive/parallel dis- tinction together with the encoding/retrieval distinction, we can distinguish among four forms of collective memory. COLLECTIVE MEMORY 143 In cases of parallel encoding/parallel retrieval , there is signifi cant interaction among group members at neither stage of the process; each individual learns and recalls on his own. While it might seem odd to include such cases under the heading of collective memory at all, they do correspond to the small-scale “nominal groups” (groups of non-interacting individuals) used in collaborative recall experiments (Weldon and Bellinger 1997; Barnier et al. 2008). At the level of large-scale collective memory, they may correspond

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    12 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us