The Fallacy of Composition

The Fallacy of Composition

University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8 Jun 3rd, 9:00 AM - Jun 6th, 5:00 PM The Fallacy of Composition James E. Gough Red Deer College Mano Daniel Douglas College Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Gough, James E. and Daniel, Mano, "The Fallacy of Composition" (2009). OSSA Conference Archive. 61. https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA8/papersandcommentaries/61 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Conference Proceedings at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Fallacy of Composition JAMES E. GOUGH AND MANO DANIEL Philosophy Red Deer College 110 College Boulevard Red Deer, AB T4N 5Y4 Canada [email protected] Philosophy Douglas College 700 Royal Ave. New Westminster, BC V3M 5Z5 Canada [email protected] ABSTRACT: The fallacy of composition involves differing relationships of parts to wholes complicated by the problem of group ambiguity. Our discussion begins with a brief diagnosis of important features of the fallacy. We consider a common implicit assumption and the main factors that contribute to its acceptability. Our focus will be on illuminating some common strategies rather than formal material conditions for the fallacy. This is to facilitate the critical discussion of possibilities for this fallacy. KEYWORDS: absolute property, aggregation, composition, collectivity, distributive, group ambiguity, parts-whole relationship 1. INTRODUCTION It is quite surprising that many critical thinking textbooks do not contain any significant discussion of the fallacies of composition and division.1 Even in the ones that do offer an account of the fallacies, the explication is often superficial and cursory. Many of the same sorts of examples are recycled and there is an alarming lack of examples from actual arguments. Concocted examples are created to match or satisfy the specific features of the fallacy of composition and not natural arguments which are discovered from everyday discourse. Moreover, there is a tendency for the fabricated textbook examples to be less than serious failures in reasoning with some examples bordering on attempts at humour. 1 For a non-prejudicial, non-systematic and not necessarily representative set of such texts, which seem to provide no reference or insufficient treatment of the fallacy of composition, see Wright (1989), Cederblom and Paulson (1996), Nosich (1982) and Hoaglund (1984). Texts which emphasise approaches to informal logic which focus on formal logic and those which do not give much emphasis to the fallacy approach to evaluating reasoning would for these reasons not give much attention to the fallacies of composition and division. Gough, J. E. and M. Daniel (2009). The Fallacy of Composition. In: J. Ritola (Ed.), Argument Cultures: Proceedings of OSSA 09, CD-ROM (pp. 1-10), Windsor, ON: OSSA. Copyright © 2009, the author. JAMES E. GOUGH AND MANO DANIEL For example, the claim that: “All members of the Toronto Maple Leaf hockey team are good hockey players, so the team is a good hockey team” generates a humorous response from those who know the team’s poor scoring record over the last forty years and this is significant because this humour may be at the expense of genuine insight. To understand under what conditions a mistake in reasoning occurs can help to prevent its occurrence in the reasoning of those so informed. As Nolt points out, many created instances of the mistake “are just silly” and are not worthy of much serious consideration nor likely to be committed by intelligent arguers.2 This paucity of explication in textbooks is lamentable since the fallacy is easy enough to commit and nocuous enough to avoid committing. For the purposes of this paper, we will focus our attention on the fallacy of composition although the same sorts of considerations apply to division since they are “opposites.” 3 Our discussion will begin with a brief diagnosis identifying some of the important features of the fallacy. We then consider a common implicit assumption and the main factors that contribute to the acceptability of this assumption. Finally, an evaluation of three actual examples of fallacious composition allows us to further explicate when it has been committed and how to learn from it. Our focus will be on illuminating common strategies and procedures rather than providing formal material conditions for the fallacy.4 2. A BRIEF DIAGNOSIS OF THE FALLACY We begin with an introductory example. Economics has two sub-branches that are related as part to whole and so the discipline is particularly susceptible to the fallacy of composition. In the move from micro to macro-economics, key concepts in one are often transformed into the other since reasoning applicable in one sphere may be maladaptive in the other. The Paradox of Thrift is a case in point. If you, as an individual, decide to save more, and reduce your debts, you will increase your wealth. But if everyone in the economy were to save more of their income and cut back on their consumption, this may reduce national wealth. The reduced incomes of one group of individuals may lead to reduced purchases by them which in turn may cause a further reduction in the income of others by reducing sales, the production of goods, the income of producers and their employees, and finally national saving and investment. What is reasonable at the micro level may have devastating ramifications when compounded at the macro; especially for an economy in the grips of a recession. One can call this an unintended, but painful consequence but one should not be surprised at this outcome. This situation is paradoxical only if one uncritically affirms the claim that what is good (or true) for the part is equally good (or true) for the whole. And, as we shall show, the status of this assumption is problematic since at some times it is appropriate but at other times it is not. Understanding this assumption and the conditions that determine its acceptability or unacceptability is crucial to a theoretical understanding of fallacious composition. 2 See Nolt (1984, p.258). See also, Damer, (2001, p.112) who points out that “some cases of the fallacy of composition are so obviously flawed that we have probably never heard them uttered.” 3 Our analysis of the fallacy of composition applies to its opposite, the fallacy of division. They are (it is generally agreed ) “two sides of the same counterfeit coin” as outlined in Woods and Walton (1977, p.381). 4 See Barker in (1989, pp. 163-164) who provides a formal response indicating that “this argument cannot be correctly translated into a syllogism, for we cannot word it so as to consist of categorical sentences containing just three terms.” 2 THE FALLACY OF COMPOSITION The fallacy of composition has to do with the relationship of part to whole compounded or exacerbated by the problem of group ambiguity. Here is a representative definition, by Halverson (1984, p.73), of the transgression: The fallacy of composition consists in treating a distributed characteristic as if it were collective. It occurs when one makes the mistake of attributing to a group (or a whole) some characteristic that is true only of its individual members (or its parts), and then makes inferences based on that mistake. Put differently, a term that is used distributively in the premises is interpreted collectively in the conclusion as one shifts from a consideration of the parts of a whole to a statement about the whole itself. Historically, attention to the fallacy has followed one of two trajectories.5 One tradition arises from the account of the fallacy presented in the Sophistical Refutation and concerns an explication of linguistic confusions that arise where the sense of a statement changes depending on whether the speaker combines what is divided or divides what is combined. The modern understanding of the fallacy, and the one that concerns us here, is genealogically affiliated with the treatment of extra-linguistic parts and wholes found in the Rhetoric where the error lies with “the assumption the hearer is meant to supply” (Tindale 1999, p. 170). Key to understanding the fallacy is to note the difference between collective (the group as a whole) and distributive (the individual members of a group) predication. For example: The Sutter (well-known Canadian hockey family) brothers hockey players are both numerous and talented. The property of being numerous is being predicated of the Sutter brothers hockey players as a group (i.e., collectively), whereas the property of being talented is being predicated of each of them individually (i.e., distributively). Fallacious composition consists in treating a distributed characteristic as if it were a collective. It occurs when one makes the mistake of attributing to a group (or a whole) some characteristic that is true only of its individual members (or its parts), and then make inferences based on that mistake. The composition fallacy is best understood as a problem complicit with and complicated by group ambiguity because it results from the fact that ordinary language often fails to make clear whether a term is being used to identify a property that refers to the members of the group individually or whether the same term is used to identify a property that refers to the group collectively. The composition fallacy can work in the opposite direction while exhibiting the same general problems of distribution as in the claim “the biggest raise increase ever given by the province” which is a case in point.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    11 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us