Distrust That Particular Intuition: Resilient Essentialisms and Empirical Challenges in the History of Biological Individuality

Distrust That Particular Intuition: Resilient Essentialisms and Empirical Challenges in the History of Biological Individuality

Distrust That Particular Intuition: Resilient Essentialisms and Empirical Challenges in the History of Biological Individuality DRAFT Finished copy will appear in E Pluribus Unum, ed. Lynn Nyhart and Scott Lidgard, publisher and date TBA. James Elwick York University Abstract There seem to be three intuitions about biological individuality that are held in western culture. This paper calls these intuitions about essences anatomical essentialism, physiological essentialism, and developmental essentialism. These intuitions reinforce one another. They work to a certain extent, and any explanation using one of the essentialisms tends to be accepted by an audience more easily. Yet when held unreflectively such intuitions lead to an impoverished understanding of individuality. These intuitions are highly resilient – histories of biology show how they have been challenged both analytically and empirically, yet they still persist to this day. I suggest this is because they both depend on and reinforce notions of purity, stability, indivisibility and autonomy. Keywords: biological individuality; essentialism; Darwin; intuitions; parasitism; chimerism; levels of individuality; holobiont Each living creature must be looked at as a microcosm - a little universe, formed of a host of self-propagating organisms, inconceivably minute and as numerous as the stars in heaven. (Darwin, 1868, p. II.404) Stop focusing on biological individuals as entities and start seeing biological individuals as systems or relationships! Such points have been insisted upon since the 1930s or 1940s, by Ludwig von Bertalanffy or Georges Canguilhem (Gayon 1998, 308), or even the 1870s by Herbert Spencer (Gissis, this volume). All well and good, and many of the papers here are written in support. But the history of biology shows that such a habit is a difficult one to break. Despite repeated empirical demonstrations that biological individuals are not always tidy physical entities, this view is one to which people continuously return. I suggest this is because we intuitively individuate by imaginary essences. "Essences" and "essentialism" are fraught terms in biology, especially in discussions about species and implications for natural kinds (Rieppel 2010; Wilson et al. 2007; Winsor 2006). They are used here reluctantly because only "essence" seems to convey the ontological intuitions I want to describe, and because only "essentialism" can capture the epistemological intuitions. The truly uncomfortable reader might use "intuitive pattern" in their place. Such difficulties reflexively illustrate how words can come to fail us when we try to articulate ourselves about biological individuality. I suggest one intuitively individuates by using three kinds of essences in biology. The first is a spatial/anatomical/formal essence that takes the guise of a particular shape, which when physically divided ends the unity of the biological individual. The second is a physiological/energetic essence which behaves as a particular optimal state, such as health, Elwick Draft 1 and anything detracting from that state can be seen as "foreign" to the biological individual. The third is a developmental/genetic essence, a specific pattern persisting over time, which when altered fundamentally changes the individual. For brevity I will refer to these individuating intuitions respectively as anatomical essentialism, physiological essentialism, and developmental essentialism. Anatomical, physiological and developmental essentialism have been repeatedly challenged empirically as new discoveries have undermined our intuitions about biological individuality. Hence anatomical essentialism was challenged in the early 1740s by the the discovery that the freshwater polyp Hydra viridis could regenerate after sectioning. Physiological essentialism has recently been challenged by findings that human physiological functions are assisted by various commensal and mutualistic microorganisms, not simply hindered by parasitic or pathological microbes. Developmental essentialism was challenged by the discovery in the early 1840s that certain jellyfish and parasites alternated between two distinct morphological forms during development. Yet these essentialisms live on. Why? One reason is because each of the three essentialisms is strengthened by associations with purity and pollution, one way in which we filter our perceptions of the world (Douglas 1966, 36-37). Consider the popular contemporary intuition that each individual's genome is unchanging and unique - a form of developmental essentialism. We know this to be false, not only because genomes do change over time, but because of rare but major exceptions such as genetic chimerism, in which a single person develops out of a fusion of two separate cell lineages that otherwise would have been fraternal twins. Sometimes such people end up questioning whether this chimerism renders their selves multiple (Martin 2007, 221). Even renowned philosophers and bioethicists are guided by intuitions about individuality too. For instance, Jürgen Habermas's views on the advisability of different forms of medical genetic engineering – between good "repair" and bad "enhancement" - pivot upon developmental essentialism (Habermas 2003), although he should know better (see critique in Barnes and Dupré 2008, 232). Meanwhile governments and courts since the 1980s have used the assumption that individual people have unchanging genomic identities to make rulings. (Martin 2007, 206-7, 212). Yet these three individuating intuitions also live on because they are often useful. They are not always incorrect, and nicely describe the world to a certain extent. For instance, physiological essentialism may be a reason why the germ theory strikes such a chord with the general public: not only does it work, but it nicely chimes with our intuitions about purity and pollution. The same point might be raised for the hypothesis of the "genetic bottleneck" as an explanation for unicellularity, to be discussed below: it appeals to an intuition of developmental essentialism. Any model or image or metaphor must oversimplify if it is to coordinate action between different people – how else could people communicate with one another if not by abstraction? A third reason for the resilience of these essentialisms is because they fit with the cherished Western belief that each one of us is a unique being possessing agency and autonomy. This is partly fostered by beliefs in individual rights and responsibilities (Martin 2007, 222). But it also seems to emerge from a tendency most recently pointed out by Barry Barnes and John Dupré – the Durkheimian insight that rather than see agency and autonomy emerging out of a set of relationships that a person has with other people, these properties tend to be situated within the individual herself (Barnes and Dupré, 2008).1 I expand upon this point in more detail below. My task as historical commentator is to put these papers into some sort of larger historical pattern. What follows has two sides. On the one hand the story is something classically and unfashionably progressive. It is a tale of a "Copernican shift": a series of discoveries which gradually undermined our easy intuitions about biological individuality, Elwick Draft 2 making individuality relativistic, dependent upon the researcher's perspective. Compare modern-day informatic perspectives on individuality with ancient depictions of a "soul" to see just how much change has occurred. It is a long way from incorporeal essences to defining an individual as a set of coordinated processes minimally necessary for that set to remain autonomous (Krakauer et al., this volume). The story of progress is not simply a tale of a move towards a greater array of explanations and perspectives: towards pluralism. It is also a shift towards a less-intuitively appealing world - if such a move can be called a progressive one. Yet on the other hand there seems to be something more fragile. There is a constant danger of a person reverting back to intuitive conceptions of individuality, even when that person should know better. This danger of reversion is partly because the three essentialisms are easy to think with, and partly because audiences sometimes only seem to listen to points that appeal to intuitive individual essences. If there is an implicit tragedy here, it is that appeals to individual essences will always find large audiences, even if those appeals are oversimplifications. By way of an analogy, consider the many histories of science showing how science is a social process (simply because science happens to be done by groups of people)…consistently overshadowed in popular culture by biographies about lone scientific geniuses.2 The problem is not that there are many brilliant people in science, as there clearly are – it is that this kind of science history is an impoverished view of how science works. The same holds true for thinking about biological individuality: our intuitions are insufficient for a complete understanding of it. <space> Intuitions of biological individuality: three essentialisms <space> There may be cognitive reasons for individuating by essence. Observing cross- cultural similarities, the anthropologist Scott Atran argued that intuitively perceiving living kinds may belong to our ability as humans to "fast-map" the world, an ability we share with other metazoa. When classifying animals, people in widely different cultures usually focus on vertebrates, placing them in different major groups;

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    16 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us