
Art fighting its way back to aesthetics Revisiting Marcel Duchamp’s Fountain Anne Elisabeth Sejten Claiming that ‘art is not what you think it is,’ Donald Preziosi and Claire Farago recall certain deep layers of art, layers that have been forgotten, repressed, occulted, or simplified beyond all recognition but layers that are working paradoxically in an ‘unsaid’ and ‘missing’ way when it comes to received ideas about art, artistic agency, and artistic experience.1 Whereas art historians as well as theorists of various orientations have challenged art theory in arguing for the increasing impossibility of defining art for the simple reason of its exploding character during the twentieth century, Preziosi and Farago argue to the contrary. Notably, they draw – if not exclusively – upon an erudite amount of religious and anthropological prehistory of art in order to show how sacral and ritual dimensions inform and interact with received ideas about art. A more or less hidden theological legacy proves to work at the core of our understanding of modern art. If things have changed in the field of art, and changed dramatically within contemporary art, Preziosi and Farago systematically confront those changes with what has not changed. A complex ‘art matrix’ thus comes to reflect a topology of art since, beyond historical changes and ruptures, art keeps responding to relations that are preserved under continuous deformations. Even though stretched and contorted, thoughts and ideas about art are structurally and virtually rebuilt upon the same topological suspensions, the same old sets of relationships, even when reproduced in displaced form in modern discourses of art. These cross-readings, convincingly presented as deconstructive ‘incursions’ into a comprehensive landscape of modern discourses on art, are illuminating and most welcome. Explicitly avoiding any desire for ‘a new ontology of art,’2 the authors steadily keep in focus the ‘historical conjunction’ between the two extremes of defining art – ‘art as universally spiritual and art as the product of a particular culture’ – insisting on art’s ‘very oscillatory power’ and its ‘unresolvability’.3 So what is at stake in Art Is Not What You Think It Is is less art succumbing to the confusion of a permanent de-definition of art,4 than the fact that art proves to be much more – and something else – than what we think it is. That is why philosophical aesthetics, closely tied to the Enlightenment and the European modern system of arts, necessarily comes under pressure. Aesthetics, however, encounters a similar challenge regarding its deeper, complex meaning, while 1 Donald Preziosi and Claire Farago: Art Is Not What You Think It Is, Chichester: Wiley- Blackwell, 2012. 2 See Preziosi and Farago, Art Is Not What You Think, xi. 3 Preziosi and Farago, Art Is Not What You Think, 45. 4 See Harold Rosenberg, The De-definition of Art, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1972. Journal of Art Historiography Number 15 December 2016 Anne Elisabeth Sejten Art fighting its way back to aesthetics Revisiting Marcel Duchamp’s Fountain current assumptions about aesthetics might generate spontaneous objections along the lines of: ‘aesthetics is not what you think it is.’ The refusal of aesthetics is not only ‘prehistorically’ stated by Plato long before its foundation in the second half of the eighteenth century, but runs almost parallel to the history of the discipline. If it took aesthetics a couple of millennia to be acknowledged in its own right, scepticism already arises in the nineteenth century, starting with Schopenhauer and Hegel, who subordinate aesthetics to the idealistic philosophical systems they were both edifying. Schopenhauer turns down aesthetics as something rather technical in the name of a metaphysics of the beautiful,5 while Hegel in reality replaces aesthetics, understood literally as a science of sensation, with a philosophy of fine art.6 Aesthetics, in either case, should certainly not begin with the sensation of the beautiful but with the Idea of beauty. Even for Heidegger, it seems imperative to reject aesthetics, which, because it implies humanism and subjectivity, misses the artwork’s potential openness to Being. Preziosi and Farago further trace the transformation of aesthetics into a philosophy of art in recent philosophy when they take into account the criticism of aesthetics from Heidegger to Giorgio Agamben.7 Simultaneously, they consider the inevitable loss of aesthetic quality in relation to a culture in which high art and consumerism have become increasingly inseparable. However, thanks to their topological approach, the difference between artistic creations and mere commodities and between the autonomy of art and commodification remains intact or, so to speak, operative, which once again questions aesthetics as much as art. Obviously, aesthetics and art do not represent, nor do they constitute, identical or converging realms of objects, and contemporary art indeed testifies to the caesura running through the humanities that splits art and aesthetics apart even further. When declaring the decline of aesthetics, art historians as well as philosophers often refer to Marcel Duchamp as an emblematic example. His readymades are clearly artistic, because they are made or conceived by an artist, but apparently they have no real aesthetic quality. Preziosi and Farago rephrase this aesthetic insufficiency in more semiotic terms, linking Duchamp to Modernism and its fundamental problem of ‘the opacity of the image in relationship to its meaning.’8 However, what does it mean to qualify Duchamp’s readymades as artistic, but not as essentially aesthetic? Doesn’t such a statement imply reducing aesthetics to the aesthetics of the Beautiful? And the Beautiful implicitly taken in its most common and less philosophically unfolded sense? Without reopening the Kantian legacy, which is certainly at stake in these questions, I would suggest revisiting the iconic case of Marcel Duchamp’s Fountain in order to discuss the prevalent assumption that contemporary art has eventually abandoned the realm of aesthetics. 5 See A. Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, trans. Richard E. Aquila in collaboration with David Carus, New York: Longman, 2008, Third book. 6 See G.W.F. Hegel, Aesthetics. Lectures on Fine Art, “Prefatory Remarks,” trans. T.M. Knox, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998. 7 See Preziosi and Farago, Art Is Not What You Think, 134-135. 8 Preziosi and Farago, Art Is Not What You Think, xi. 2 Anne Elisabeth Sejten Art fighting its way back to aesthetics Revisiting Marcel Duchamp’s Fountain Two rejections and one counterattack Two renowned rejections might serve to orchestrate the discrepancy between art and aesthetics within Duchamp himself, all the more spectacularly as in both cases they took place in cutting edge artistic milieus. In 1912, Duchamp’s Nude Descending a Staircase (no. 2) was, if not directly refused, somehow censured by the French ‘Indépendants’ at their Salon of 1917. The Cubist group of painters had kindly let Duchamp know that they wanted him to redraw the painting, which he did. Their hostility might surprise, because this painting connects more to Cubism than it breaks with it, especially through the colour scale, through the way in which a human figure is converted into cubes and surfaces, and through the way Duchamp introduces new dynamic effects by painting the movement of a descending person in several of its almost simultaneous displacements. Perhaps the scrupulous exploration of human movements provoked the hostility to Duchamp, as if his approach to the human figure was accused of being too repellent, too dehumanizing. Whatever the reasons of his Parisian friends, Duchamp experienced the refusal as a betrayal of their otherwise shared belief in the very ‘independence’ of art and the artist. In spite of being the latest avant-garde, the Cubists’ response appeared to be characterized by certain dogmatism. In any case, Duchamp was resolutely determined to test once again the independence of the artist’s own democratic, open-minded organisations and even renew his passion for industrial mass production when, five years later in 1917, he submitted – or rather arranged to be submitted – his famous Fountain to the inaugural exhibition of the newly established Society of Independent Artists in New York. By submitting a common urinal that he had turned upside down and signed by a pseudonym, Duchamp certainly wrote art history. An ordinary, manufactured object was designated by an artist to be a work of art. But to become one of Duchamp’s most famous works and even an icon of twentieth-century art, it is bewildering to recall that the original piece hardly had time to exist before it was lost, only to become resurrected decades later as replica during the sixties before entering into the most prestigious collections of modern art. Actually, as few other artworks in modern times, this lost readymade is surprisingly veiled in mythologizing secrecy, probably increased by the fact that the only thing which is left of the original is the photograph that Alfred Stieglitz took in his gallery a few days after the official exhibition opening. It is even hard to establish the true history of Fountain, which remains haunted by various contradictory versions that keep on circulating.9 Because Duchamp himself was a distinguished member of the board of directors at the New Yorker Society of Independent Artists, he went undercover as a certain ‘R. Mutt’, whose
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages8 Page
-
File Size-