Some Remarks on Intention in Action John Mcdowell

Some Remarks on Intention in Action John Mcdowell

Some Remarks on Intention in Action John McDowell The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy lectureP 6, 2011 http://www.amherstlecture.org/ the amherst lecture in philosophyP Lecture 6, 2011 Some Remarks on Intention in Action John McDowell Preferred citation McDowell, John. “Some Remarks on Intention in Action.” The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy 6 (2011): 1–18. <http://www.amherstlecture.org/mcdowell2011/>. Abstract I suggest that intentions for the future become intentions in action when the time for acting comes. The image of intentions as a kind of continuant helpfully accommodates progress in an action; a persisting intention in action changes its shape in respect of how much of what is intended lies behind it and how much is still in prospect. Specific motor intentions in the course of, for instance, crossing a street are shapes successively taken by a persisting inten- tion in action. I argue against the idea that an intention in action relates de re to the action it is in. Finally, adapting Brian O’Shaughnessy’s dual aspect conception of the will, I propose that when one intentionally engages in bodily action, the action’s intentional character is an aspect of something that is also bodily through and through. The result stands in contrast with familiar philosophical pictures of the relation between mind and body. The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy (ISSN: 1559-7199) is a free on-line journal, published by the Department of Philosophy, Amherst College, Amherst, MA 01002. Phone: (413) 542-5805. E-mail: [email protected]. Website: http://www.amherstlecture.org/. Copyright John McDowell. This article may be copied without the copyright owner’s permission only if the copy is used for educational, not-for-profit purposes. For all other purposes, the copyright owner’s permission is required. In all cases, both the author and The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy must be acknowledged in the copy. the amherst lecture in philosophyP Lecture 6, 2011 Some Remarks on Intention in Action John McDowell University of Pittsburgh 1. Philosophers sometimes treat “intention in action” as a technical term.1 But a concept expressible with that phrase can be easily made out to be no more than part of common sense. I want to sketch a way of conceiving intention in action that we can be in command of just by being familiar with relevant regions of our ordinary language. 2. To begin isolating something we might mean by “intention in action,” we can distin- guish it from intention for the future. An intention in action is an intention that is in the course of getting executed, so it is contemporaneous with doing whatever it is an intention to do. In that respect an intention in action stands in contrast with a prior intention, an in- tention to do such-and-such at some future time. A prior intention predates the action that is its execution, if indeed there is any such action, as there will not be if the person who has the intention is prevented or changes her mind or forgets. One can do something intentionally without having had a prior intention to do it. One can act intentionally on the spur of the moment. But we can ask: when doing something in- 1 Robert B. Brandom hyphenates it into a single word, which implies that he is not treating it as a bit of ordinary language; see Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1994). John Searle also hyphenates it in Rationality in Action (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2001). In Intentionality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), he left it as three words. Some Remarks on Intention in Action John McDowell 1 the amherst lecture in philosophyP Lecture 6, 2011 tentionally is doing something one had a prior intention to do, how does the prior intention relate to the intention in action we implicitly acknowledge when we say the doing is inten- tional? I am going to begin working up to a picture of intention in action by considering an answer to this question given by John Searle. I think Searle’s answer is helpful as a contrast to a different picture that I want to recommend. On Searle’s account, intentions in action are new items that a prior intention starts to generate when the time to execute it comes. Prior intentions and intentions in action are different even apart from the difference in their temporal relation to stretches of activity. A prior intention has as its object an action, doing such-and-such at some future time. But an intention in action, generated by the prior intention at its due time, has as its object not the action the agent is embarking on, but something Searle conceives as a component of it. Consider, for instance, an intention harboured by someone standing on a kerb: the intention to cross the street when the light turns green. On Searle’s account, when she sees the light turn green, that intention – a prior intention, an intention for the future – starts to generate intentions in action. The object of the intention for the future is crossing the street; the objects of the intentions in action that it generates are the limb movements that need to happen if the person is to cross the street. As those limb movements begin, she begins crossing the street. If all goes well, she gets to the other side, thereby completing an action of crossing the street. On Searle’s account, the action is a causally structured complex: its components are, first, the intentions in action that the prior intention began to generate when the agent saw the light turn green, and, second, the limb movements on which the intentions in action are targeted, which the intentions in action will have caused. I think it is clear that this is a bit of philosophical theory, not a spelling out of ways we learn to think just by learning to talk about acting intentionally. And I do not think Searle would dispute that. He would say there are philosophical purposes for which his theory is needed. I am not going to try to assess this claim directly. I have cited Searle’s theory only as a foil, to bring into relief a different answer to the question how intentions in action are related to intentions for the future. I would claim that the different answer is more natural, and if that is right, it cannot be irrelevant to the philosophical purposes for which Searle thinks we need his theory. But I am not going to attend to that for its own sake. Some Remarks on Intention in Action John McDowell 2 the amherst lecture in philosophyP Lecture 6, 2011 On this different account, when one sees the light turn green and starts crossing the street, it is not that an intention for the future starts to generate new items, intentions in action as Searle conceives them. Rather, what was an intention for the future becomes an intention in action. When one starts to do something one had a prior intention to do, say crossing the street, one’s intention, now in action, is still directed at crossing the street, not at the limb movements that need to happen if one is to do that. In saying what the prior intention was an intention to do, one mentions a time: when the light turns green, in my example. When its time comes, what was a prior intention takes a new shape as an intention in action, provided the agent does not forget the intention, knows the time has come, is not prevented from acting accordingly, and does not change her mind. What were prior intentions become intentions in action, on this picture, through the operation of an ability to keep track of time. My street-crossing case involves a very simple instance of that ability. One determines the time for acting as the time at which a recogniz- able thing is going to happen: one’s intention is to cross the street when the light turns green. When that recognizable thing happens and the subject recognizes that the time has come, the intention becomes an intention in action. That is just another way to say she starts doing what she intended, and still intends, to do. Of course the ability to keep track of time has more sophisticated forms also. And of course its relevance to a subject’s psychological history is not restricted to the way inten- tions persist through time. The ability to keep track of time is operative whenever one keeps hold of time-specific thoughts as time passes. For instance, one can retain for a while a bit of knowledge one could express, when one acquired it, by saying “The light is turning green.” One needs to express it differently later, perhaps by saying “The light turned green a while ago.” It is the same bit of knowledge, persisting through the passage of time, that needs to be expressed in these different ways. Just so, it is the same intention, persisting through the pas- sage of time, that alters from being an intention for the future to being an intention in action when its time comes, provided that it does not lapse through change of mind or forgetfulness, and provided that the agent knows its time has come and is not prevented from acting.2 2 On keeping track of time, see Gareth Evans, The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982), especially 192–6. Some Remarks on Intention in Action John McDowell 3 the amherst lecture in philosophyP Lecture 6, 2011 3.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    20 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us