Romanticism: Philosophy and Literature

Romanticism: Philosophy and Literature

View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Works Swarthmore College Works Philosophy Faculty Works Philosophy 2014 Romanticism: Philosophy And Literature Richard Thomas Eldridge Swarthmore College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-philosophy Part of the Philosophy Commons Let us know how access to these works benefits ouy Recommended Citation Richard Thomas Eldridge. (2014). 2nd. "Romanticism: Philosophy And Literature". Encyclopedia Of Aesthetics. https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-philosophy/257 This work is brought to you for free by Swarthmore College Libraries' Works. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Works. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Encyclopedia of Aesthetics (2 ed.) Edited by Michael Kelly Publisher: Oxford University Press Print Publication Date: 2014 Print ISBN-13: 9780199747108 Published online: 2014 Current Online Version: 2014 eISBN: 9780199747115 Romanticism. To analyze the meaning and history of Romanticism both as a distinct period of art and as a general aesthetic category, this entry comprises three essays: P L V A M The first essay examines the philosophical roots of Romanticism and the development of Romantic literature. Because Romanticism has had different histories in the various arts, there are separate essays on the visual arts and music. For related discussions, see Aestheticism; Autonomy: Overview; Difficulty, Aesthetics of; Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich; Kant, Immanuel; Novalis; Originality; Primitivism; Schiller, Johann Christoph Friedrich von; Schlegel, August Wilhelm von; and Schlegel, Karl Wilhelm Friedrich von. Philosophy and Literature Romanticism begins in an experience of anxiety at one’s possible human unreality, an anxiety that is strongly voiced by Immanuel Kant in the Critique of Judgment and closely associated with him by his philosophical and literary successors. “How,” Kant asks, “can I express my freedom and rationality, somehow lodged deep within me noumenally, in a phenomenal world ordered under physical causal laws?” “The concept of freedom is meant to actualize in the sensible world the end proposed by its laws.” How? And if I can’t thus actualize my freedom and rationality, what then am I? Perhaps I am capable of nothing more than the “almost savage torpor” that William Wordsworth saw in his urban countrymen (“Preface to Lyrical Ballads,” 1801). The achievement of expressive freedom, in writing and in life, is then seen as the task of humanity, as it seeks to raise itself out of mere naturalness and to achieve its vocation in culture. As Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe and Jean-Luc Nancy cogently observe, Kant’s “weakening of the subject” ontologically as a being no longer present to itself in inner intuition “is accompanied by an apparently compensatory ‘promotion’ of the moral subject which … launches a variety of philosophical ‘careers’ ” (1988). In German Idealist philosophy, the effort is to overcome various forms of division—subject-object, value-fact, freedom-nature, consciousness-the unconscious, self-other—by systematically describing a developing metaphysical order that undergirds both nature and humanity, explains the present existence of those divisions, and secures the possibility of overcoming them to achieve expressive freedom. Romanticism, in contrast, is more self-critical in pursuing this same ambition. Romantics are characteristically more aware that their efforts at expression arise out of and remain marked by the divisions that they wish to escape. They remain in anxiety about their receptions by their audiences. Their best works—in a generalization that holds true for Wordsworth, Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Percy Bysshe Shelley, John Keats, Lord Byron, Friedrich von Schiller, and Friedrich Schlegel—are characteristically either incomplete, or fragmentary, or self-critical, or finally ironic. This has led Lacoue-Labarthe and Nancy to speak of a “literary absolute” that is sought and imperfectly, infinitely, enacted in their works, and it has similarly led Jerome McGann (1983) to distinguish between a doctrinal “Romantic ideology” of the overcoming of dualisms and the more troubling, more self-critical work of “Romantic poetry” that never quite accomplishes its longed-for transformations. The wish for achieving full humanity through expressiveness, coupled with an enduring anxiety about the possibility of success, while arguably simply part of human consciousness of temporality, also arises with special intensity around 1790, in part out of occasioning social-political and scientific circumstances. The development of a widespread commercial and early industrial economy, particularly in England, in the sixty or so years before 1790 led to increased division of labor and social mobility. Writers and other artists began to make their livings, when they could, through publication, performance, and sales, rather than through patronage. The necessities of doing this, and the uncertainties of reception in a divided economy, led to increased anxiety about both the specific offices of art and the possibility of expressing humanity generally. Rather than seeing humanity expressed collectively in the partial Click to view larger conformity of social structures to a divinely ordained archetype, individuals Helvoetsluys; - the City of Utrecht, 64, Going to Sea, 1832 (oil on began to worry about how to win their particular places in the market. As the canvas), Joseph Mallord William Turner. conditions for the expression and ratification of rationality, humanity, and © , / freedom become more uncertain and tenuous, Schiller notes the “negative results of divided labor” (“On the Aesthetic Education of Man”), and Wordsworth alludes to “a multitude of causes, unknown to former times” (“Preface”) that are acting to degrade the fitness of social life for humanity. At the same time, human beings, as a result of the seventeenth-century revolution in mathematical physics and its associated achievements in engineering, are now beginning to possess greater powers to free themselves from natural misery, and hence more scope for the expression of individual personality. There is, in 1790, no going back to any ruder, premodern state without the benefits of technology. The effort is instead to blend modern achievements with more stable simplicities, to blend what Schiller called “the naive”—the pastoral, in which mind and nature are one, often identified with the pre-Socratic Greeks—with “the sentimental,” the modern realm of dividedness and self-consciousness. The movement of the imagination on the whole is forward toward synthesis, toward “something evermore about to be” (Wordsworth, Prelude), not backward. The French Revolution, with its ideals of liberty, equality, and fraternity, is seen as an especially promising, but then desperately failed, response to these modern social conditions and plights of mind. After the September Massacres of 1792, the Terror of 1793–1794, and the growing domination of Napoleon from 1795 onward, writers increasingly turn inward in attempting to take up the Revolution’s ambitions and to avoid its failures. The transfiguration of humanity comes to be posited or announced proleptically, in art or within the subject, not immediately in politics, though the difficulties of proclaiming a message that requires a new audience in order to be received lead such proclamations typically to be crossed by despair, self-doubt, or irony. Romanticism’s aims for humanity thus contrast powerfully with the ancient world’s pursuit of naturalness and eudaimonia, with medieval Christianity’s ideals of obedience, continence, and beatitude, and with the Enlightenment’s commitment to scientific understanding, material improvement, and satisfaction. Instead of any of these, expressiveness, or what Wordsworth and Ralph Waldo Emerson call “Power,” is the aim, wherein subjective personality and social reciprocity support one another rather than being locked in conflict. Social peace is to be won without sacrificing individuality and spontaneity. A number of thematic and stylistic features distinguish the Romantic writing that pursues this aim from its predecessors: 1. There is a prominent retrospective stance that expresses a consciousness of fallenness or dividedness. “Was it for this … ?” Wordsworth asks about his present impotent state in the Prelude in undertaking to review his life; “That time is past, / And all its aching joys are now no more, / And all its dizzy raptures,” he laments in “Tintern Abbey.” In his 1808 “Lectures on Dramatic Art and Literature”—the principal critical document on Jena Romanticism for both Madame de Staël and Coleridge, who transmitted its analyses to France and England, respectively—August Wilhelm von Schlegel remarks that “The Grecian ideal of human nature was perfect unison and proportion between all the powers—a natural harmony. The moderns, on the contrary, have arrived at the consciousness of an internal discord which renders such an ideal impossible.” This consciousness of discord and division traces back to Schiller’s essay “On Naive and Sentimental Poetry,” and before that to Kant’s remarks in his historical and anthropological essays on humanity’s fitful progress through alienation. In France, it is expressed in Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s opposition to the idea that the arts and civilization have led to an improvement in manners; in

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    6 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us