
Saint Louis University Public Law Review Volume 31 Number 2 General Issue (Volume XXXI, No. 2) Article 5 2012 The Two Countermajoritarian Difficulties Or Bassok Yale Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.slu.edu/plr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Bassok, Or (2012) "The Two Countermajoritarian Difficulties," Saint Louis University Public Law Review: Vol. 31 : No. 2 , Article 5. Available at: https://scholarship.law.slu.edu/plr/vol31/iss2/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Saint Louis University Public Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarship Commons. For more information, please contact Susie Lee. SAINT LOUIS UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW THE TWO COUNTERMAJORITARIAN DIFFICULTIES OR BASSOK* ABSTRACT In recent years, the countermajoritarian difficulty has split into two. According to its traditional version, the difficulty arises when unaccountable Justices strike down statutes passed by electorally accountable branches of government. According to the newer, literal version, the difficulty arises when Justices strike down statutes that are supported by the majority according to public opinion polls. By explicating the difference between the two versions of the difficulty, I expose the deep influence of public opinion polls on American constitutional thought. For many years, scholars conflated the two difficulties under one banner and offered normative justifications for the Court’s countermajoritarian authority. In recent years, many constitutional theorists, oriented toward social science, attempt to dissolve the literal countermajoritarian difficulty by showing that the Court is not countering the majority will but following it. I further demonstrate that the distinction helps to explain four additional issues of constitutional theory. First, this distinction explains the connection between the countermajoritarian difficulty and the “passive virtues” technique that Alexander Bickel devised for the Court. Second, it exposes the importance of the distinction between cases that the media covers and non-visible cases. Third, it sheds new light on the basis of the Court’s power. Finally, this distinction is crucial for a better understanding of a puzzle that stands at the heart of the rise of judicial power worldwide. * Robina Foundation Visiting Human Rights Fellow, Yale Law School; LL.M, Yale Law School; LL.M & LL.B, Hebrew University of Jerusalem. I am extremely grateful to Bruce Ackerman, Jack Balkin, Paul Kahn and Robert Post for many illuminating discussions and thoughtful comments. I wish also to thank Kiel Brennan-Marquez, Robert Burt, Yoav Dotan, Noam Y. Finger, James E. Fowkes, Alon Harel, Shay Levi, Han Liu, Lucas Mac-Clure, Itamar J. Mann- Kanowitz, Fernando L. Munoz, Erin L. Miller, Iddo Porat, and participants at the 2011 Yale Law School Doctoral Scholarship Conference and the College of Management Law School faculty workshop for helpful comments on earlier drafts. All mistakes are my own. 333 SAINT LOUIS UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW 334 SAINT LOUIS UNIVERSITY PUBLIC LAW REVIEW [Vol. XXXI:333 TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................... 335 I. DISTINGUISHING BETWEEN THE TWO CM DIFFICULTIES ....................... 337 A. Historical Background .................................................................... 337 B. Conceptual Analysis ........................................................................ 339 II. JUSTIFYING THE COURT’S CM AUTHORITY ........................................... 343 A. Rights-Based Arguments ................................................................. 344 B. Process-Based Arguments ............................................................... 345 C. Dworkin’s Empire ........................................................................... 346 D. Textualism and Originalism ............................................................ 347 E. Ackerman’s Dualist Model .............................................................. 348 III. DISSOLVING THE CM DIFFICULTY IN ITS LITERAL SENSE ...................... 350 A. Robert Dahl Plants the Seeds for Dissolving the Literal CM Difficulty ......................................................................................... 350 B. Dissolution Mechanisms ................................................................. 352 1. The Appointment Process ........................................................ 352 2. Strategic Behavior and Attitudinal Change .............................. 354 3. Backlash Theories .................................................................... 355 4. Public Opinion as a Legitimate Legal Argument ..................... 357 C. What is Left of the CM Difficulty? .................................................. 358 IV. BICKEL AND THE TWO CM DIFFICULTIES .............................................. 362 V. VISIBLE CASES ....................................................................................... 367 VI. JUDGMENT VS. PUBLIC CONFIDENCE ..................................................... 368 VII. THE CM DIFFICULTY IN ITS LITERAL SENSE GOES ABROAD ................. 376 CONCLUSION: THE TWO CM DIFFICULTIES IN THE TWENTY-FIRST CENTURY ........................................................................................................ 380 SAINT LOUIS UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW 2012] THE TWO COUNTERMAJORITARIAN DIFFICULTIES 335 INTRODUCTION The countermajoritarian (hereinafter “CM”) difficulty is changing. Long before Alexander Bickel conceptualized the problem and gave it its catchy name,1 the tension between constitutionalism and democracy was understood to arise from the authority of unaccountable judges to invalidate legislation enacted by electorally accountable representatives.2 This conceptualization of the CM difficulty, to which I refer as “traditional,” has obsessed American legal academia for decades.3 The main tactic for tackling it has been to propose justifications for the Court’s CM authority.4 Following the invention of scientific public opinion polls and especially with the rise of “public-opinion culture,”5 a second understanding of the CM difficulty has emerged. According to this literal understanding, the difficulty arises when the Court decides to invalidate legislation that enjoys the support of the majority of the population, as captured by public opinion polls before the decision or shortly thereafter.6 The “literal” nature of this formulation of the difficulty is embedded in the premise that “majority will” is scientifically measured by public opinion polls. Scholars find this premise controversial, yet 1. ALEXANDER M. BICKEL, THE LEAST DANGEROUS BRANCH: THE SUPREME COURT AT THE BAR OF POLITICS 16 (1962). 2. See Barry Friedman, The History of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty, Part One: The Road to Judicial Supremacy, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 333, 342–43 (1998) (acknowledging “some limited countermajoritarian criticism in virtually every era in American history”); Robert W. Bennett, Counter-Conversationalism and the Sense of Difficulty, 95 NW. U. L. REV. 845, 846 (2001) (“Bickel was certainly not the first to express concern about judicial review, nor the first to associate that difficulty with the nondemocratic nature of the courts.”). 3. See, e.g., Friedman, supra note 2, at 334 (“The ‘countermajoritarian difficulty’ has been the central obsession of modern constitutional scholarship.”); Richard H. Pildes, Is the Supreme Court a “Majoritarian” Institution?, 2010 SUP. CT. REV. 103, 104 (“[I]t is not wrong to characterize American legal thought as ‘obsessed’ with the moral problem of judicial review.”). 4. See Daryl J. Levinson, Parchment and Politics: The Positive Puzzle of Constitutional Commitment, 124 HARV. L. REV. 657, 659 (2011) (“[T]he leading question in constitutional theory for generations has been how to justify constitutional limitations on the authority of democratic majorities given our background commitments to popular sovereignty and self- government—the infamous ‘countermajoritarian difficulty.’”). 5. See, e.g., BRUCE ACKERMAN, THE DECLINE AND FALL OF THE AMERICAN REPUBLIC 75 (2010) (“Right or wrong, decades of polling have had a profound impact on the public mind.”); SUSAN HERBST, NUMBERED VOICES: HOW OPINION POLLING HAS SHAPED AMERICAN POLITICS 12 (1993) (“Quantitative surveys, both scientific and unscientific, are now a pervasive component of public discourse . .”). 6. See, e.g., Barry Friedman, Mediated Popular Constitutionalism, 101 MICH. L. REV. 2596, 2596 (2003) (“There is a regrettable lack of clarity in the relevant scholarship about what ‘countermajoritarian’ actually means. At bottom it often seems to be a claim, and perhaps must be a claim, that when judges invalidate governmental decisions based upon constitutional requirements, they act contrary to the preferences of the citizenry. Some variation on this premise seems to drive most normative scholarship regarding judicial review.”). SAINT LOUIS UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF LAW 336 SAINT LOUIS UNIVERSITY PUBLIC LAW REVIEW [Vol. XXXI:333 it is undisputed in the public discourse where polls’ results are presented as the will of the people.7 While justifications of the Court’s CM authority are usually formulated in a manner that allows them to confront the literal version of the difficulty, the distinct main tactic for tackling this version has been to dissolve it, by showing
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages51 Page
-
File Size-