
Wh-movement: multiple questions and islands, overt and covert (3) Superiority effect: subject vs. object Incorporation a. Who __ bought what? The nature of the grammar b. *What did who buy __? (4) Superiority effect: higher object vs. lower object [If you're also looking at the handouts, this summary starts with section 2 of the second wh handout.] a. Who did you persuade __ to read what? 3 1. Multiple Questions b. *What did you persuade whom to read __? What is a multiple question? The existence of the Superiority effect suggests that C "gets to pick" what wh moves to it. We may view the C as "attracting" the wh-phrase to it. We call this the "Attract Closest" A multiple question is a question that contains more than one wh-word, whose answer is a property of movement: set of sentences in which each of the wh-words is replaced by an appropriate non-wh expression that makes the answer true. (5) Attract Closest When a head attracts a phrase with a particular property to its specifier, it picks the Example: closest phrase with that property. (1) a. Question: Who bought what? Answer: Mary bought the book, John bought the calculator, Sue bought the computer, etc. 2. Movement in general: the "Minimalist Program" b. Question: Who did you persuade to read what? Let's spell out how this works in slightly more detail. Terminology: "wh-in-situ" A wh-phrase that does not undergo wh-movement1 is said to remain in situ, and is sometimes referred to as wh-in-situ. In a multiple question in English, one wh-phrase undergoes wh-movement. Other wh- phrases remains in situ. The model I am sketching here is a model associated with research in the so-called This means that before wh-movement takes placein a multiple question, there is more than Minimalist Program. The name "Minimalist Program" comes from a 1993 paper (and one wh-phrase that potentially could undergo wh-movement. In fact, there is normally no 1995 book) by Noam Chomsky, and reflects work done by a number of researchers in the freedom in such constructions. 1990s. There are other approaches that differ to varying degrees from "Minimalism". (2) The "Superiority Effect" • A head is made of features (properties). When IP contains two wh-words, the one that undergoes wh-movement is the one • Some of these features -- called uninterpretable features -- are "active". What this 2 closest to the interrogative C. means is explained in the next bullet. Here are some examples: • An uninterpretable feature acts as a probe, looking down the tree for the closest matching instance of the same feature -- called a goal. The relationship between probe and goal is called agreement, and sometimes expresses itself as morphological agreement. 1 At this point, the class had not yet discussed the possibility of covert wh-movement. In this summary, "wh-movement" always refers to overt wh-movement. In a multiple question, it can be argued that the wh- phrases that do not move overtly do move covertly -- an idea that I did not stress and perhaps failed to mention in class. 3 The handout contained a third set of examples that raises interesting questions about PPs and what 2 There are exceptions that have been studied. For example, when instead of who and what we have such "closest" means in (2). For present purposes, however, we will disregard the issue. The examples were: phrases as which person and which book, many speakers find that the Superiority effect disappears or at least a. Who did John talk to __ about what? weakens. b. *What did John talk to whom about __? -2- • If the probe also has a [generalized version of the] EPP property, some constituent that (7) Agree (Probe-Goal relation) without movement: the there construction contains the goal will move to the probe, forming a specifier of the probe. a. There is a puppy in the garden. b. There are puppies in the garden • What constituent containing the goal moves? -->If the goal (or its maximal projection) is the sister of the probe, the result is head c. There seems to be a puppy in the garden. movement. d. There seem to be puppies in the garden. -->Otherwise, it is usually the maximal projection of the goal that moves, but sometimes something larger. These are the mysteries of pied piping. Here, EPP for I is satisfied by there, not by the goal DP that is discovered by the probe ϕ- features on I. That is why I agrees not with its specifier, but with that goal DP (a puppy or • The same story holds for wh-movement, as discussed below. In wh-movement, the puppies). probe is the uninterpretable wh-feature of C. [The DP with which I agrees in the there construction must typically be an "indefinite DP" In a nutshell: semantically, e.g. There is a puppy in the garden not There is the puppy in the garden, Step 1: If the head has an uninterpretable feature uF, it acts as a probe, looks down with there expletive.4 The exact nature of the definiteness effect in there constructions is the tree for a goal. If probe is successful --> agree. quite an interesting matter, which you might get a chance to study in the Semantics class Step 2: If uF is also +EPP --> movement. — 24.903. There has been much research on the question.] Note: The "attract closest" property holds of agree. Example #2: Interrogative C attracting a wh-phrase. • In wh-constructions, an interrogative C has an uninterpretable uWh feature (what we early called "+wh") that acts as a probe for another element (its goal) that bears Example #1: I attracting the subject. interpretable wh. If it finds such an element, C agrees with it. Finite I in English bears uninterpretable person and number features uPerson and • If uWh on interrogative C also has the EPP property -- which it does in English -- uNumber. These features, along with uGender (uNoun-Class) in languages that some constituent that contains the wh goal undergoes movement to Spec,CP. That's have this, are collectively known as ϕ-features ("phi-features"). wh-movement! These ϕ-features act as a probe, looking for an element that bears interpretable instances of Person and Number. If it finds such an element (e.g. a DP in Wait a minute! We don't see morphological agreement between C and wh in English. Spec,VP), I agrees with it. We see this as overt number and person agreement True, but we do in Kinande: between I and the subject: (8) Wh-C agreement in Kinande (Bantu, NE Congo) (6) Subject-I agreement a. IyondI yO kambale alangIra. a. The puppy is in the garden. who (cl.1) that (cl.1) Kambale saw b. The puppies are in the garden. c. I am in the garden. b. aBahI Bo kambale alangIra. who (cl.2) that (cl.2) Kambale saw I also has the EPP property, which means it needs a specifier. Typcally, the specifier is provided by the DP with which I agrees. That's why movement occurs: DP moves in c. EkIhI kyO kambale alangIra. order to become the Specifier of IP. what (cl.7) that (cl.7) Kambale saw (Schneider-Zioga 1987; quoted in Rizzi 1990) As a bonus, nominative case is assigned to DP in this position. Do we ever see Agree between I and DP without Move? The English expletive there construction provides us with an example: 4 Except as a "reminder" answer: "I'm starving, and there's nothing to eat in the house. What could we cook for dinner?" "Well... there's the puppy in the garden..." No I don't really mean it... -3- 3. How structures are built 4. Multiple Specifiers Bottom to top (a standard view in the Minimalist Program) Sometimes, an uninterpretable feature keeps probing for new goals, even after Agree has already taken place with the closest goal. If the feature is also EPP, we find Structure-building is accomplished by two very similar rules: Merge and Move. multiple movement, forming multiple specifiers. This is what we find in multiple questions in Slavic and other East European languages (including Yiddish). Merge: 5 a. Combine 2 [or more] lexical items or previously formed phrases, forming a new phrase. What's interesting is how the wh phrases are ordered. The closest wh to C moves first. b. Designate one as the head, which labels the phrase, in accordance with X-bar theory. The next-closest "tucks in" under it. Here are examples from Bulgarian: c. If necessary, before a modifier or specifier merges with a head, create a single-bar projection of the head with which the modifier merges. You could think of this as the Bulgarian result of merging a head with itself, if you're so inclined ("identity merge"). No, we d didn't discuss this in class. I blurred over this.6 c (9) a. Koj kogo __ vižda __ ? Move: who whom sees If an uninterpretable feature uF of a head H has an EPP property, it may be satisfied by ‘Who sees whom?’ the following steps: 1. make a copy of the constituent with which uF agreed (its goal); 2. merge it as the specifier of H (i.e. as a sister of H' above all modifiers). b.*Kogo koj __ vižda __? Notice that Merge differs from Move mainly in whether the material that "grows the tree" whom who sees from the bottom up is provided externally (from the lexicon or form material already built in another "workspace") or internally (by copying material in the current tree).
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages10 Page
-
File Size-