P. 1 Math 490 Notes 3 Continuing Our Overview of Set Theory, There Are Set

P. 1 Math 490 Notes 3 Continuing Our Overview of Set Theory, There Are Set

p. 1 Math 490 Notes 3 Continuing our overview of set theory, there are set operations which parallel all of the usual operations in arithmetic. We previously mentioned the formation of a quotient set A/S = {S(x) x ∈ A} relative to an equivalence relation S on A. If A has n elements and each equivalence class (under S) has k elements, then A/S has n/k elements. Unions are es- sentially set “addition”; when A and B are disjoint sets with n and k elements, respectively, then A ∪ B has n + k elements. Set differences corresponds to subtraction. To form set exponents, it is useful to first extend the definition of set products. Let {Xi i ∈ I} be an arbitrary collection of sets, and let X = {f : I → X f(i) ∈ X for all i ∈ I}. i i ∈ i I X is called the Cartesian product of the X , denoted by X = X . Note that each func- i i i∈I tion f ∈ X is a function which chooses a representative element, f(i), from each set Xi. Such a function is often referred to as a “choice function”, and its existence is a consequence of the Axiom of Choice. Also note that X = φ iff Xi = φ for some i ∈ I. In dealing with set prod- ucts, it is common to write f ∈ ∈ Xi as f =(xi)i∈I , where f(i)= xi. If I = {1, 2,...,n}, i I then f would be the n-tuple (x1, x2,...,xn). If I = N, then f would be the sequence (xn)n∈N. Set exponentiation is simply a special case of set product. If A and I are sets, and Xi = A for all i, then ∈ Xi can be thought of as the product of A with itself ”I times”, and we write i I I I ∈ Xi = ∈ A = A . By the earlier definition of ∈ Xi, it follows that A is simply i I i I i I the set of all functions from I into A. If A and I are finite sets with n and k elements, respectively, then AI contains nk elements. Note that Rn = RI , where I = {1, 2,...,n}, and RN is the set of all (infinite) sequences of real numbers. p. 2 The power set P(X) of all subsets of X is often written via exponential notation. Let ”2” denote the set {0, 1}, and for any subset A of X, let χA denote the characteristic function of A: 1, x ∈ A χ A = . 0, x ∈ X − A Then every f ∈ 2X is the characteristic function of some subset of X, and each subset of X is uniquely defined by its characteristic function. Thus P(X) can be identified with 2X . Cardinal Numbers Cardinal and ordinal numbers are not considered in Munkres, but both are frequently used in topology, so we’ll discuss them briefly here, beginning with cardinal numbers. Let A and B be sets. Define A . B to mean that there exists a bijection between A and a subset of B. Also define A ∼ B to mean that there is a bijection between A and B. Then ∼ is an equivalence relation, and A ∼ B =⇒ A . B and B . A. Schr¨oder-Bernstein Theorem If A and B are sets, then A ∼ B iff A . B and B . A. It is natural to ask, ”On what set are the relations . and ∼ defined?”. The answer would seem to be the ”set of all sets”, but that answer is not consistent. If there were a set S of all sets, consider the subset A of S defined by A = {B ∈ S B ∈ B}. Then by definition, if A is an element of itself, then A ∈ A, and if A is not an element of itself, then A ∈ A. This contradiction is known as Russel’s Paradox. We can avoid this paradox by saying that . and ∼ are relations on the class of all sets, denoted here by S. p. 3 The equivalence classes into which S is partitioned by ∼ are called cardinal numbers. Like S itself, the cardinal numbers are a class which we’ll call C. The equivalence class consisting only of φ is called ”0”; the equivalence class consisting of all singleton sets is called ”1”, etc. The equivalence class containing N is called ℵ0, and the equivalence class containing R we’ll denote by 2ℵ0 . If α and β are cardinal numbers, we define α ≤ β to mean ∃A ∈ α and ∃B ∈ β such that A . B. One can check that ≤ is a well-defined partial order on C. Note that the anti-symmetry of ≤ follows from the Schroder-Bernstein Theorem. Indeed, it can be shown that ≤ is a simple order using another equivalent version of the Axiom of Choice called the Well Ordering Theorem; more to come about that. The smallest infinite cardinal is ℵ0. A set is countable iff its cardinal number is ≤ ℵ0, and is otherwise uncountable. The distinction between countable and uncountable sets is important in analysis, so you may have seen various proofs of the facts that sets like Z and Q are countable, whereas R, R − Q, and the Cantor Set are uncountable. It is also well-known that countable unions and finite products of countable sets are countable. We’ll conclude this discussion of cardinal numbers by briefly considering cardinal arithmetic. For any set A, let |A| denote the cardinal number of A. Given two cardinal numbers α and β, choose A ∈ α and B ∈ β such that A ∩ B = φ. It is not customary to define cardinal subtraction or division, but the other operations are defined as follows: α + β = |A ∪ B|; αβ = |A × B|; αβ = |AB|. For finite cardinals, cardinal arithmetic reduces to ordinary arithmetic. p. 4 Propostion N3.1 If α, β, γ are arbitrary cardinal numbers, then: (a) Cardinal addition and multiplication are both commutative and associative; (b) α(β + γ)=(αβ)+(αγ); (c) α(β+γ) = αβαγ; (d) (αβ)γ = αγβγ; γ (e) αβγ = αβ . Propostion N3.2 Let α, β be cardinal numbers with α ≤ β and β infinite. Then: (a) α + β = αβ = β; (b) If α ≥ 2, then αβ > β. Proof of (b): If α ≥ 2, then 2β ≤ αβ, so it suffices to show β < 2β. Then we know {0, 1}∈ 2, and we can choose some B ∈ β. As discussed previously, the set 2β can be regarded as (is in one-to-one correspondence with) the power set of B. The fact that |B| ≤ |2B| should be fairly clear; considering the injection from B to its singleton subsets gives us B . P(B) ∼ 2B. Now, we show that no bijection exists between B and 2B (i.e. B ∼ 2B). Suppose, on the contrary, that there is a bijection g : B → 2B. Let A = {b ∈ B b ∈ g(b)}. Then A ∈ 2B, so ∃ a ∈ B such that g(a)= A. Now, if a ∈ g(a), then a ∈ A, and g(a)= A (a contradiction). If a ∈ g(a), then a ∈ A, and g(a)= A (a contradiction). So no element of B can map to A, and consequently g can not be a bijection. ¥ Well Ordered Sets The theory of well ordered sets provides the foundation for the study of ordinal numbers. A well ordered set (w.o.set) is a poset in which every non-empty subset contains a least element. p. 5 Proposition N3.3 Every well-ordered set is simply ordered. Proof: Let X be a well ordered set, and let x, y ∈ X. Then the subset {x, y} must contain a least element, which is either x or y. If it is x, then x ≤ y. If it is y, then y ≤ x. Thus X is a poset which also satisfies the comparability axiom, and is therefore simply ordered. ¥ Every w.o.set contains a least element, but not every simply ordered set with a least el- ement is well ordered. For example, [0, 1] (with the usual ordering) has a least element 0, but the subset (0, 1) does not. Every finite simply ordered set is well ordered, as is the set N of natural numbers. If A and B are disjoint well ordered sets, then A ∪ B can be made into a w.o.set by stipulating that (a ∈ A and b ∈ B) =⇒ a < b, while leaving the orders within A and B unchanged. For instance, suppose A = {a0,a1,...,an,...} and B = {b0, b1, . , bn,...}, where the elements of these sets are listed in increasing order from left to right. Then A ∪ B = {a0,a1,...,an, . , b0, b1, . , bn,...}, with elements again listed in increasing order from left to right, is a w.o.set. Furthermore, for any w.o.sets A and B, the set A×B is well ordered relative to the dictionary order. Any subset of a well ordered set with the inherited order is also well ordered. In a simply ordered set X, b is the immediate successor of a iff a < b and a<c ≤ b =⇒ c = b. The immediate predecessor is defined similarly. Proposition N3.4 In a w.o.set X, every element which is not the greatest element of X has an immediate successor, but every element does not necessarily have an immediate pre- decessor. Proof: Let a be an element of X which is not the greatest element. And let b be the least element of {x ∈ A a < x}, which is is non-empty. Then b is the immediate successor of a. In the example mentioned previously involving A ∪ B, neither a0 nor b0 has an immediate predecessor.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    6 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us