Economics of Social Policy

Economics of Social Policy

Economics of Social Policy Miguel Gouveia Faculdade de Ciências Económicas e Empresariais UNIVERSIDADE CATÓLICA PORTUGUESA Results from Welfare Economics - 1 ! General equilibrium in Edgeworth boxes: consumption α with endowments, 2 consumers, 2 goods. ω 0 ! 1st Welfare Theorem: The allocation of resources that results from a competitive equilibrium is Pareto Optimal 1st Theorem - illustration ! 2nd Welfare Theorem: If preferences and technology are convex given a Pareto optimal resource allocation α we can find a competitive equilibrium that generates that resource allocation. That β equilibrium is obtained by a suitable ω distribution of the initial endowments in 0 the economy. 2nd Theorem - illustration2 1 Results from Welfare Economics -2 2 G o α o β ω d 0 Transfer of good y from consumer y ω 1 to consumer 2 1 1 Good X Endowment transfers Transfer of good x from consumer correspond to “lump- 1 to consumer 2 sum” taxes U2 In this example the redistribution from consumer 1 to 2, from consumption vector α to consumption vector β, corresponds to a move along the utility β possibility frontier α U31 Results from Welfare Economics - 3 ! Is it the case that the 2nd Welfare Theorem implies that there is no tradeoff between efficiency and equity? Can we do any redistribution without compromising efficiency? ! No. There are endowments that cannot be U redistributed. Ex: time, intelligence, 2 SWF2 creativity, energy, physical abilities and β characteristics (highly valued by the SWF market), etc. φ 1 α ! Political decision makers have to choose U1 between efficiency and equity. Their “values” can be analytically represented by Social Welfare Functions- SWFs 4 2 Results from Welfare Economics -4 U2 ! Negishi’s Theorem.Consider a Social β welfare function of the form α SWF= ∑ λ U . i i U1 ! Then, the allocation and utility distribution that maximizes this SWF is Pareto optimal for positive λ’s. Moreover, if the utility possibility frontier is convex, for any allocation A and utility distribution U that is Pareto optimal there is a vector of welfare weights λ’s such that A and U are the solution to the SWF maximization problem. 5 Fair Allocations 1 ! SWF are defined over the space of individual utilities and they summarize ethical judgments and moral values. But the implications of these judgments are sometimes difficult to evaluate. ! Also it is interesting to examine issues of fairness directly in the space of goods (allocations). ! If we have a total endowment in the economy of goods x and y given by (X, Y) and n individuals equally deserving, most would agree that giving each individual a vector (X/n, Y/n) is a fair allocation. Intuitively, there is an ethical appeal to symmetry. ! But is the equal division allocation efficient? NOT NECESSARILY because people have different tastes. 6 3 Fair Allocations 2 In this case, the symmetric ω allocation e is outside the contract ω curve and thus is Pareto inefficient. e This example shows symmetry is not a good criterion for judging an allocation. Inefficiency of equal division ω Naturally, we can improve on e if we allow for trade among agents. Are all allocations obtained from trading starting at an equal division equitable? NOT NECESSARILY. If n=3 and persons 1 and 2 have the same preferences whereas 3 is different, and 1 and 3 trade and make themselves better off, then 2 will be worse off than 3 and evaluate the post trade allocation as unfair. 7 Fair Allocations 3 How can we define an equitable allocation? By a NO ENVY condition. An allocation is equitable if no agent prefers another agent’s bundle of goods to his own. In an Edgeworth box that means an agent does not prefer to swap allocations with the other agent. ω! i ω! s ω Allocation i is envy free or equitable since no one would like to trade places. But it is not efficient. 8 4 Fair Allocations 4 ! We know the set of all efficient allocations is the contract curve. What is the set of all envy free allocations in an Edgeworth box? 2 ! ! 1 envies 2 ! ! 1 Envy boundary for 1 9 Fair Allocations 5 ! We first build the envy boundary for agent 1, then for agent 2 and then take the intersection. No envy Mutual envy 2 2 envies 1 1 envies 2 Mutual envy 1 No envy 10 5 Fair Allocations 6 ! The set of FAIR allocations is the intersection of the sets of efficient allocations, the contract curve, and the set of all envy free allocations. 2 1 Fair allocations 11 Fair Allocations 7 One way to find fair allocations is to look for a competitive equilibrium started from an equal division of the endowments. In this case no agent envies other agents. 2 ω e 1 12 6 Fair Allocations 8 ! The fact that a competitive equilibrium from equal division is a fair allocation tells us that the market is not only efficient but also fair provided endowments are equitably allocated to begin with. ! This may be interpreted as saying the market is fair as a process. ! Unfortunately, there are limits to the significance of the result. In production economies envy-free and efficient allocations may not exist – we go back to the problem that some endowments simply cannot be redistributed. 13 Fair Allocations–Cobb-Douglas Example 1 1 2 ! Preferences: U =lnx1+2lny1 U =2lnx2+lny2 ! Endowments: X=20 Y=10 ! The set of Fair allocations has all efficient and envy-free allocations. ! Contract curve MRS1=MRS2 ⇔ y1/2x1= 2y2/x2 ⇔ y1/2x1 = 2(10- y1)/(20-x1) : solving for y1 we find y1 =40 x1/(20+3x1). ! Points in the contract curve: (x1=0,y1=0), (x1=4,y1=5), (x1=10,y1=8), (x1=20,y1=10), Contract Curve 10 9 8 7 6 Y 5 4 3 2 1 0 0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 16 18 20 X 14 7 Fair Allocations–Cobb-Douglas Example 2 1 ! The envy free frontier for agent 1 is defined by: U = lnx1+2lny1 = ⇔ 2 2 2 ln(20-x1)+2ln(10-y1) x1=20(10-y1) /(y1 +(10-y1) ) 2 ! The frontier for agent 2 is U =2lnx2+lny2=2ln(20-x2) + ln(10-y2) , 2 2 2 y2=10(20-x2) /(x2 +(20-x2) ). For the purpose of graphical representation we can re-write 2’s frontier in terms of x1 and y1: 2 2 2 ⇔ 2 2 2 10-y1=10(x1) /(x1 +(20-x1) ) y1=10(20-x1) /(x1 +(20-x1) ) Envy Frontiers 10 9 8 7 6 Y 5 4 3 2 1 0 0 2 4 6 8 101214161820 15 X y2 y1 Fair Allocations–Cobb-Douglas Example 3 ! Fair allocations are a subset of the contract curve y1 =40 x1/(20+3x1). 2 2 2 The intersection at the envy frontier 1, x1=20(10-y1) /(y1 +(10-y1) ), gives us y1=6,14 and x1=6,39. 2 2 2 ! 2’s frontier, in terms of x1 and y1 , is y1=10(20-x1) /(x1 +(20-x1) ). The intersection is y1=7,16 and x1=7,73 Fair Allocations 10 7.73; 7.16 8 6 Y 6.39; 6.14 4 2 0 0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 16 18 20 X y2 y1 cc 16 8 Fair Allocations–Cobb-Douglas Example 4 ! Finally, let us check that the competitive equilibrium from equal division is Fair. There are two goods but by Walras’ Law we only need to calculate the equilibrium in one market. Normalize the price of x to 1 (only relative prices matter). ! The consumer’s problem is λ Max x,y L = lnx1+2lny1 + [10-x1 –p(5-y1 )]. ! Solving the First order conditions, ∂∂LL12 =−=λλ0; =− ;10 −+xp (5 − y ) = 0 ∂∂ 11 xx11 yy 11 d the demand for y1 is given by y1 =20/3p+10/3. d ! The demand for y from consumer two is y2 =10/3p+5/3. ! In the general equilibrium demand equals supply: 10= 10/3p+5/3+ 20/3p+10/3, p=2. This implies y1=20/3=6.(6) and y2 =10/3=3.(3). This also means x1=6.(6) and x2 =13.(3). 17 Fair Allocations–Cobb-Douglas Example 5 Fair Allocations 10 8 6.66; 6.66 6 Y 4 2 0 02468101214161820 X 18 y2 y1 cc 9 Assumptions of perfect competition ! Agents are price takers. – Many agents on the demand and on the supply side. Each agent is small. Market failures resulting from violation: monopoly (natural or not...), monopsony, cartels, etc. ! Resources are privately owned and used – Market failures resulting from violation: public goods, externalities ! No restrictions to the mobility of resources – Market failures resulting from violation in the form of barriers to entry and exit in certain professions or industries (sectors). ! All agents have equal access to relevant information – Market failures resulting from violation: asymmetric information problems such as moral hazard or adverse selection. 19 Welfare Measures - 1 Consumer Surplus Producer Surplus P D P S p PS = Profit + p1 1 CSEC p PSEC Fixed Costs p0 0 Q Q ! CS neglects income effects. It is an adequate measure for situations where the income effect is negligible, typically when the good has a small household budget share. ! To measure changes in some important markets such as the labor market, housing and other large household budget share goods we should use exact measures: the equivalent and the compensatory variations. 20 10 Welfare Measures - 2 ! Concepts – U(x, y) utility function; M Income; px py prices –X(M,px ,py ), Y(M, px ,py) demand functions –U(X(M,px ,py ), Y(M, px ,py)) = V(M, px ,py ) indirect utility 0 ⇔ 0 –V(M,px ,py )= U E (U ,px ,py ) = M, expenditure function ! Compensating Variation.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    11 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us