The Symmetric Difference Is Associative

The Symmetric Difference Is Associative

THE SYMMETRIC DIFFERENCE IS ASSOCIATIVE DAVE AUCKLY This is a sample proof of a result from set theory. The most important part of a proof is a chain of facts, each of which has a supporting reason. To make this clear in the following proof, I will put each fact in blue text and each reason in red text. A formal proof should have the following parts: (1) A declaration. This is a word or two to let the reader know that a statement to be proved is about to be given. For example, Theorem, Lemma, or Proposition. (2) A statement of the fact that is to be proved. This should be a complete sentence and not an imperative. (3) Something to indicate the start of the proof, e.g., \proof'." (4) The guts of the proof which is a chain of facts and reasons leading to the statement that was to be proved. (5) Something to indicate the end of the proof. What do I use to mark the end of the following proof?? It is possible to include comments in a proof. Comments make it easier for the reader to read the proof, but are not necessary for the proof. The proof works just fine if all comments are left out. I will use green text for the comments in the following proof. Comments about the comments will be in cyan. Theorem 1. For any three sets A, B and C we have (A∆B)∆C = A∆(B∆C): Proof. Since the definition of equality for two sets (X = Y ) is containment in both directions, i.e., X ⊆ Y and Y ⊆ X the proof will split into two parts. We indicate this with a comment at the start of the proof. We first show that (A∆B)∆C ⊆ A∆(B∆C). Let x 2 (A∆B)∆C by hypothesis. The reason we are starting like this is that the definition of X ⊆ Y is that x 2 X implies that x 2 Y . This has the structure of an if-then statement. The if part is called the hypothesis and we are given that the hypothesis is true. Our goal is to prove the then statement, i.e., the conclusion. Thus, x 2 ((A∆B) [ C) n ((A∆B) \ C) by the definition of symmetric difference. We conclude that x 2 ((A∆B) [ C) and x2 = ((A∆B) \ C) by the definition of set difference. Continuing we see that either x 2 (A∆B) or x 2 C by the definition of union. After an either-or statement, the proof splits into cases with one case for each possible given or statement. 1 2 DAVE AUCKLY Case 1: x 2 (A∆B) By the definition of symmetric difference we have x 2 (A [ B) n (A \ B). It is possible to put the reason before the fact. Thus x 2 (A [ B) and x2 = (A \ B) by the definition of set difference. By the definition of union, Either x 2 A or x 2 B. Case 1.1: x 2 A It follows that x 2 A [ (B∆C) by the definition of union. We no proceed indirectly to show that x2 = B. Assume x 2 B. OK This is certainly weird the first time you see it. In an indirect proof we assume some statement *without* justification. After arriving at a contradiction we conclude that something must be wrong and the only thing that could be wrong is the assumption. This proves that the assumption was wrong. This implies that x 2 A \ B by the definition of intersection. This contradicts the fact that x2 = A \ B that was already established under the hypothesis of case 1. The assumption must therefore be false, so x2 = B. Proceed indirectly. Assume x 2 C. Since x 2 (A∆B) by the hypothesis of case 1, the definition of intersection implies that x 2 (A∆B)\C. However, before we split into cases, we established that x2 = (A∆B) \ C. This contradiction means that the assumption that x 2 C is false, i.e., x2 = C. One more time we proceed indirectly. Assume x 2 A \ (B∆C) The definition of intersection then gives x 2 B∆C. Thus, x 2 B [ C by the definition of symmetric difference. It follows that either x 2 B or x 2 C by the definition of union. This contradicts the facts established in this subcase that x2 = B and x2 = C by logic. We conclude that the latest assumption was false, i.e., x2 = A \ (B∆C). By the definition of set difference we have x 2 (A [ (B∆C)) n (A \ (B∆C)). The definition of symmetric difference then shows that x 2 A∆(B∆C) in case 1.1. Case 1.2: x 2 B We would now need to proceed to show that x 2 A∆(B∆C) in case 1.2. After establishing some fact in both cases, or in this example subcases, we close this part of the argument as follows. In either case 1.1 or case 1.2 x 2 A∆(B∆C). Case 2: x 2 C We would probably need to split this into subcases as well. Again we would be trying to establish that x 2 A∆(B∆C) under the conditions of case 2, so we could conclude that it was always true. The proof would continue... By the definition of symmetric containment( A∆B)∆C ⊆ A∆(B∆C). This is now the halfway point in the proof. It is good to include a comment to let the reader know where things stand. We now show that (A∆B)∆C ⊇ A∆(B∆C). Let... After the large second block, the proof would end as follows. Since (A∆B)∆C ⊆ A∆(B∆C) and (A∆B)∆C ⊇ A∆(B∆C), the definition of set equality gives( A∆B)∆C = A∆(B∆C). .

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    2 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us