Uncorrected Version

Uncorrected Version

JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 1 SESS: 66 OUTPUT: Mon Oct 6 17:21:13 2014 SUM: 8397CB03 /Xpp84/wiley_journal_P/PAPQ/papq_v0_i0/papq_12048 Toppan Best-set Premedia Limitedbs_bs_query Journal Code: PAPQ Proofreader: Mony Article No: PAPQ12048 Delivery date: 29 Sep 2014 Page Extent: 29 1bs_bs_query 2bs_bs_query 3bs_bs_query THE IF P, OUGHT P 4bs_bs_query 5bs_bs_query 1 PROBLEM bs_bs_query 6bs_bs_query 7bs_bs_query BY 8bs_bs_query 9bs_bs_query JENNIFER CARR 10bs_bs_query 11 bs_bs_query 12bs_bs_query Abstract: Kratzer semantics for modals and conditionals generates the predic- 13bs_bs_query tion that sentences of the form if p, ought p are trivially true. As Frank and 14bs_bs_query Zvolenszky show, for certain flavors of modality, like deontic modality, this 15bs_bs_query prediction is false. I explain some conservative solutions to the problem, and 16bs_bs_query then argue that they are inadequate to account for puzzle cases involving 17bs_bs_query self-frustrating oughts. These cases illustrate a general problem: there are two 18bs_bs_query forms of information-sensitivity in deontic modals. Even generalizations of 19bs_bs_query Kratzer semantics that predict these two roles for information, e.g. Kolodny 20bs_bs_query and MacFarlane predict that they vary together. I propose a generalization of 21bs_bs_query Kratzer semantics that allows the two information roles to vary independently 22bs_bs_query of each other. 2 bs_bs_query 23bs_bs_query 24bs_bs_query Introductory modal logic told us that modals quantify over possible 25bs_bs_query worlds: ought p is true iff p is true at all worlds within in a specified domain. 26bs_bs_query And the popular restrictor analysis of conditionals told us that condition- 27bs_bs_query als are a kind of modal: if p, q is true iff q is true at a specified domain of 28bs_bs_query p-worlds. When these two views are paired, as in the familiar Kratzer 1 29bs_bs_query semantics, they have an unintended consequence: they validate: 30bs_bs_query 31bs_bs_query (1) If p, ought p. 32bs_bs_query 2 33bs_bs_query But obviously not all instances of if p, ought p are trivially true: 34bs_bs_query 35bs_bs_query (2) If you beat up elderly people, you ought to beat up elderly people. 36bs_bs_query 37bs_bs_query This point was first made about deontic conditionals under the restrictor 38bs_bs_query analysis by Frank (1997); Zvolenszky (2002, 2006, 2007) provides detailed 39bs_bs_query investigation. The point generalizes to other analyses of deontic condition- 40bs_bs_query als, and was independently discovered by van Fraassen (1972), Spohn 41bs_bs_query (1975), and Jackson (1985). Pacific Philosophical Quarterly •• (2014) ••–•• DOI: 10.1111/papq.12048 © 2014 The Author Pacific Philosophical Quarterly © 2014 University of Southern California and John Wiley & Sons Ltd. 1 JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 2 SESS: 66 OUTPUT: Mon Oct 6 17:21:13 2014 SUM: 5335E046 /Xpp84/wiley_journal_P/PAPQ/papq_v0_i0/papq_12048 2 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY 1bs_bs_query If we want to hold onto possible worlds semantics for modals and a 2bs_bs_query restrictor analysis of conditionals, how can we avoid this result? I will 3bs_bs_query argue that doing so is harder than expected. Section 1 introduces the 4bs_bs_query ‘classic’ account of modals and restrictor analysis of conditionals, and 5bs_bs_query explains how they validate if p, ought p. In Section 2, I describe some 6bs_bs_query candidate explanations for how if p, ought p can fail to be true that are 7bs_bs_query consistent with the restrictor analysis combined with possible worlds 8bs_bs_query semantics for modals. According to the most successful of these theories, 9bs_bs_query iffy oughts are systematically ambiguous between a single-modal interpre- 10bs_bs_query tation and a double-modal interpretation. Section 3 discusses a test for 11 bs_bs_query disambiguating the single- and double-modal readings, and shows that 12bs_bs_query this test gives counterexamples to the proposed account. Section 4 surveys 13bs_bs_query strategies for maintaining a conservative semantics while accommodating 14bs_bs_query tough cases. Finally, in Section 5, I provide a positive account. I show that 15bs_bs_query two forms of information-sensitivity affect the interpretation of iffy 16bs_bs_query oughts. Generalizing our account of modals to allow them to vary inde- 17bs_bs_query pendently of each other makes it possible to model and predict problem 18bs_bs_query cases. 19bs_bs_query 20bs_bs_query 1. The problem 21bs_bs_query 22bs_bs_query 1.1. A SIMPLIFIED KRATZER SEMANTICS 23bs_bs_query 24bs_bs_query Why is the schema if p, ought p predicted to be valid? Because the condi- 25bs_bs_query tional is true iff in all the best possible p-worlds, p is true. 26bs_bs_query To show this more carefully, let’s briefly rehearse the Kratzer account of 27bs_bs_query conditionals, which has long been the default theory in linguistic seman- 28bs_bs_query tics. According to Kratzer semantics, conditionals are a kind of quantified 29bs_bs_query sentence; usually involving a modal quantifier. Modals, in this view, are 30bs_bs_query given a possible worlds interpretation: ought p is true iff p is true at all the 3 4 5 31bs_bs_query best worlds that are possible, given the circumstances. , , 32bs_bs_query Two elements of this analysis are contextually determined: what’s best 33bs_bs_query and what’s possible given the circumstances. There are different ways of 34bs_bs_query modeling these two contextual parameters. Kratzer models them with two 35bs_bs_query sets of propositions (i.e. sets of sets of worlds): a modal base, which is a set 36bs_bs_query of propositions characterizing the circumstances (determining the set of 37bs_bs_query relevant possible worlds), and an ordering source, which determines a 6 38bs_bs_query pre-order over worlds. (The preorder can be used to represent the relation 39bs_bs_query of comparative deontic ideality, teleological ideality, epistemic plausibil- 40bs_bs_query ity, and so on.) 41bs_bs_query For ease of exposition, I will model these with simpler and more ideal- 42bs_bs_query ized tools: a set of worlds and a (total) ordering. (See Figure 1.) The modal 43bs_bs_query background, f, is the set of worlds that are possible given the circum- © 2014 The Author Pacific Philosophical Quarterly © 2014 University of Southern California and John Wiley & Sons Ltd. JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 3 SESS: 66 OUTPUT: Mon Oct 6 17:21:13 2014 SUM: 54B64968 /Xpp84/wiley_journal_P/PAPQ/papq_v0_i0/papq_12048 THE IF P, OUGHT P PROBLEM 3 1bs_bs_query stances (for example, epistemically possible worlds). The ordering, g, 2bs_bs_query ranks worlds in terms of ideality of some sort or other; we’ll focus on 3bs_bs_query deontic ideality. These jointly determine the domain of the modal: 4bs_bs_query 5bs_bs_query DOMAINS: domain(w, f, g) is the set of worlds in the modal back- 6bs_bs_query ground f ranked highest by the ordering g. 7bs_bs_query 8bs_bs_query The official statement of this simplified Kratzer semantics: 9bs_bs_query 10bs_bs_query MODALS: ought p is true at 〈w, f, g〉 iff p is true at all w′∈domain(w, 11 bs_bs_query f, g). 12bs_bs_query 13bs_bs_query Conditionals are, on this view, modals that have a restriction on the 14bs_bs_query modal background. The if-clause restricts that set of worlds: if p, ought q 15bs_bs_query takes the set of worlds in the modal background f and eliminates all the 16bs_bs_query worlds where p is false. ought q is evaluated relative to the remaining set of 17bs_bs_query worlds. In Figure 2, I represent restrictions diagrammatically by graying 18bs_bs_query out a portion of the modal background. 19bs_bs_query Official statement: 20bs_bs_query 21bs_bs_query CONDITIONALS: if p, ought q is true at 〈w, f, g〉 iff q is true at 22bs_bs_query domain(w, f + p, g) where ‘f + p’ is shorthand for the intersection of f and 23bs_bs_query the set of worlds where p is true. 24bs_bs_query 25bs_bs_query 1.2. THE PUZZLING CONSEQUENCE 26bs_bs_query 27bs_bs_query From here, it’s easy to see how CONDITIONALS validates if p, ought p, 28bs_bs_query relative to any world-modal background-ordering triple. if p, ought p is 29bs_bs_query 30bs_bs_query Figure 1 Modals. 31bs_bs_query 32bs_bs_query Figure 2 Conditionals. © 2014 The Author Pacific Philosophical Quarterly © 2014 University of Southern California and John Wiley & Sons Ltd. JOBNAME: No Job Name PAGE: 4 SESS: 66 OUTPUT: Mon Oct 6 17:21:13 2014 SUM: 5FE62A4E /Xpp84/wiley_journal_P/PAPQ/papq_v0_i0/papq_12048 4 PACIFIC PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY 1bs_bs_query true iff p is true in all of the g-ideal p-worlds that are possible according to 2bs_bs_query f. It’s trivial that p is true in all the p-worlds in any set of worlds. 3bs_bs_query When the necessity modal is epistemic, the triviality of if p, ought p is 7 8 4bs_bs_query unproblematic: , 5bs_bs_query 6bs_bs_query ✓ 3 (3) If it’s raining, it must be raining. bs_bs_query 7bs_bs_query (4) If she’s not home, she must not be home. ✓ 8bs_bs_query 9bs_bs_query Similarly, as Zvolenszky (2006) notes, with appropriate context, related 10bs_bs_query teleological examples may be interpreted as trivial. They are uninforma- 11 bs_bs_query tive but not false: 12bs_bs_query 13bs_bs_query (5) a. A: What do I have to do to go to Berlin? 14bs_bs_query b. B: To go to Berlin, you have to go to Berlin. ✓ 15bs_bs_query c. B: If you want to go to Berlin, you have to go to Berlin. ✓ 16bs_bs_query 17bs_bs_query But when the modal is interpreted as deontic, there are clear 18bs_bs_query counterexamples: 19bs_bs_query 20bs_bs_query (6) If

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    29 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us