Entering the Posthuman Collective in Philip K. Dick's "Do

Entering the Posthuman Collective in Philip K. Dick's "Do

SF-TH Inc Entering the Posthuman Collective in Philip K. Dick's "Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep?" Author(s): Jill Galvan Reviewed work(s): Source: Science Fiction Studies, Vol. 24, No. 3 (Nov., 1997), pp. 413-429 Published by: SF-TH Inc Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4240644 . Accessed: 19/08/2012 23:13 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. SF-TH Inc is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Science Fiction Studies. http://www.jstor.org ENTERING THE POST-HUMAN COLLECTIVE 413 Jill Galvan Entering the Posthuman Collective in Philip K. Dick's Do AndroidsDream of ElectricSheep? "The morning air, spilling over with radioactivemotes, gray and sun-becloud- ing, belched about him, hauntinghis nose; he sniffed involuntarilythe taint of death."1 Such is the atmospherethat assails Rick Deckard, protagonistbounty hunter of Philip K. Dick's Do AndroidsDream of Electric Sheep?, as he sets out upon his most lucrative-yet final-day in the business. Insidious, strange- ly menacing, the air Rick breathesconfronts him with the perils of his world, a world increasingly transformedby nuclear fallout and the forces of entropy. Additionally, it is a world progressivelypeopled-both literally and figurative- ly-by technological devices, among which the android, a "solitarypredator," seems as greatly to endanger human survival as the tainted environment(?3: 31). Against the backdrop of televisions, vidphones, and mood organs, Rick meets head-on with this consummatetwenty-first-century machine, the human- oid robot that has murderedits master in assertion of its liberty. Indeed, as much for its will to independence as for its manifest violence, the fugitive android threatens a community of authentichuman subjects: capable of mas- querading as non-android, it blends in with mainstreamsociety, infringing upon the boundariesof the humancollective. In short, the machine, by declar- ing its right to live as an autonomous self, challenges the very categories of life and selfhood-and, in turn, the ontological prerogativeof its creators. For Dick, this fictional predicamentdoes not far exaggeratethe conditions of nonfictional reality, of an existence progressively alteredby innovations in technology. In "The Android and the Human," a speech delivered four years after the publication of Do Androids Dream, Dick addressesjust this issue of a progressively blurred distinction between humans and their own mechanical creations. [O]ur environment, and I mean our man-made world of machines, artificial con- structs, computers, electronic systems, interlinkinghomeostatic components-all of this is in fact beginning more and more to possess what the earnestpsychologists fear the primitive sees in his environment: animation. In a very real sense our environmentis becoming alive, or at least quasi-alive, and in ways specifically and fundamentallyanalogous to ourselves. (183) And what can we glean from the growing animationof the things that surround us? As much about their being as about ours, Dick says: "Ratherthan learning about ourselves by studying our constructs, perhaps we should make the at- tempt to comprehend what our constructs are up to by looking into what we ourselves are up to" (184). But as Dick goes on to explain, the two explora- 414 SCIENCE-FICTIONSTUDIES, VOLUME 24 (1997) tions are not easily divisible:whether we acceptit unquestioninglyor rebel againstit, technology,in the handsof the powersthat be, has acquirednot simply a life of its own, but a life that substantiallyinfiltrates our lives, changing our characterin subtle yet meaningfulways. If we succumb unwittingly-or, worse,indifferently-to the totalitarianmechanization of our world, we risk becomingandroids ourselves, reduced to "humansof mere use-men madeinto machines"(187). To denytechnology's pervasive role in our existencemeans, then, to denyreality-the realityof a worldin whichwe areadvancingly imbricated in a mechanicalpresence. Only by recognizinghow it has encroachedupon our understanding of "life"can we cometo full terms with the technologieswe have produced. Do AndroidsDream tells the storyof one individual'sgradual acceptance of thesechanging parameters. A bildungsromanfor the cyberneticage, Dick's novel describesan awakeningof the posthumansubject. As I hopeto illustrate in the remainderof this paper,Rick Deckard'sexperience policing the boun- dariesbetween human and android teaches him to questionthe traditionalself- other dyad, which affirmsa persistenthuman mastery over the mechanical landscape.The androidsRick encounters,together with the numerousma- chinesby whichhe andothers interface with their world, blast the illusionof an exclusiveand empathic community of humans,one uncompromisedby the technologieswith whichthey sharethe Earth.Do AndroidsDream thus inter- rogatesa fixed definitionof the humansubject and at last acknowledgeshim as only one componentof the living scene. In effect, the narrativerepudiates the idea of a confinedhuman community and envisionsa communityof the posthuman,in which humanand machinecommiserate and comaterialize, vitally shapingone another'sexistence. At the novel'soutset, however, Rick has yet to rethinkthe dominantideol- ogy of the juridicalsystem that employs him. He acceptswithout contest the ontologicalcategories of his culture,according to which humans'principal differencefrom their android look-alikes lies in theirability to feel empathy. Thiscredo, which Rick adheres to in orderto identifyhis androidvictims, not only nominallyseparates human from machine, but also helps to insulatethe humancommunity: if humansalone have the powerto empathize,then their only emotionallyprofitable, mutually beneficial relationships occur with each other. The android'sdeficiency patently expels it from the collective-any collective,for thatmatter, even one of otherandroids. As the partyline goes, the androidlacks the capacityfor fellow feelingfor its own kind as muchas it does for humanbeings. "Anandroid," Rick avers, "doesn'tcare what hap- pens to anotherandroid" (?9:101). But as it gets playedout in the novel, this reputedexistential distinction runsinto irresolvablecontradictions. Notably, a few of theandroids Rick deals with exhibitwhat appears to be caringfor theirown kindand even, in some cases, for the humanswith whom they interact. N. KatherineHayles has point- ed out thatRachael Rosen, the androidwho mostpointedly calls Rick to ac- countfor his actions,shows real concernfor the six escapedandroids he has been commissionedto "retire."After seducinghim in orderto detourhim ENTERING THE POST-HUMAN COLLECTIVE 415 from his task, for example, Rachael confesses to Rick that she and one of his victims "had been close, very close friends for almost two years" (?17:199). Moreover, in both word and deed, Rachaelintimates her affection for a human -for Rick himself. "After Rick succeeds in killing the last three andys," Hayles notes, he returns home to discover that Rachael has pushed [his] goat off the roof. Why? Because she is jealous of his love for the goat, or in revenge for his killing her friends...? Whichever interpretationone chooses, the action is not consistent with the official picture of android psychology, which like Dick's essays insists that androids are incapable of feeling loyalty or indeed feeling anything at all.2 And if on the one hand androids reveal their ability to feel compassion, the reader begins to surmise, on the other hand, that what passes for "empathy" among humans derives far more from a cultural construction than from any categorical essence. The Voigt-Kampff scale-which, because it measures empathy, Rick uses to ensure the androididentity of his potentialprey-throws into relief the contrived natureof this putatively most basic of humanqualities. Almost all of the scenarios Rick poses to his respondentsstage some incident of animal cruelty-a live lobster in a pot of boiling water, a stag's head mounted on a cabin wall, a nude woman lying on a bearskin rug. Yet one quickly identifies these hypothetical situations for what they really are: instances of brutality and exploitation, yes, but not uncommon in many social contexts-in fact, too common to trigger consistent empathicreactions in most humanbeings. As JudithB. Kermanaptly puts it, the scenarios that Rick prof- fers to his android suspects would not, should they generate an apatheticre- sponse, "differentiate[androids] from modem Americans" (71). The Voigt-Kampff scale refers in large part to incidents of animalmistreat- ment because live animals, in a post-nuclearera which finds them scarce, have been fetishized as the repositories of human empathy. Additionally, though purchasingone entails a considerable expense, a live animal marks the buyer as a zealous adherentof Mercerism. The legendaryeponym of this widespread philosophy/religion, a figure persecuted by the authoritiesfor bringing dead animals back to life, encourages animal ownership as a sign of his followers' moral solidarity. Those who regularlysubmit themselves to Mercerist"fusion" endure the utmost in human empathy:

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    18 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us