Coanalytic Ranks and the Reflection Theorems

Coanalytic Ranks and the Reflection Theorems

COANALYTIC RANKS AND THE REFLECTION THEOREMS CHRISTIAN ROSENDAL 1. Coanalytic ranks A rank on a set C is a simply a map φ: C Ord. Similarly, a prewellordering 4 on C is a reflexive, transitive, and total relation! for which , defined by ≺ x y x 4 y & y $ x; ≺ , is wellfounded. From a rank φ: C Ord we can define a canonical prewellorder- ! ing 4φ on C by letting x 4 y φ(x) 6 φ(y); φ , and, conversely, from a prewellordering 4 we can define a rank φ4 by setting 8 > 4 <>φ4(x) = 0 if x y for all y C, > 2 :>φ4(x) = sup φ4(y) + 1 y x otherwise. f ≺ g Definition 1. Suppose X is a Polish space and C X is a coanalytic subset. Then 1 ⊆ φ: C Ord is said to be a Π -rank provided that the following relations 6∗ and ! 1 φ <φ∗ , defined by 6 6 x φ∗ y x C & y X C or x;y C & φ(x) φ(y) ; , 2 2 n 2 x <∗ y x C & y X C or x;y C & φ(x) < φ(y) ; φ , 2 2 n 2 are Π1 as subsets of X X. 1 × Theorem 2 (Y. N. Moschovakis). Let C be a coanalytic subset of a Polish space X. Then C admits a Π1-rank φ: C ! . 1 ! 1 Proof. By composing with a Borel reduction of C X to WO 2Q, we may suppose Q ⊆ ⊆ that actually X = 2 and C = WO. So set φ(x) = ordertype(x;<Q) and let E Q Q Q ⊆ Q 2 2 be the Borel set defined by × × (f ;x;y) E p;q Q if p;q x & p < q; then f (p);f (q) y & f (p) < f (q) 2 , 8 2 2 2 f order-embeds (x;<Q) into (y;<Q): , We then have x <∗ y (x;<Q) is wellordered and (y;<Q) does not order-embed into (x;<Q) φ , Q x WO and f Q (f ;y;x) < E; , 2 8 2 1 2 CHRISTIAN ROSENDAL 1 which is Π1. Similarly, x 6∗ y either x <∗ y or (x;<Q) and (y;<Q) are wellordered with φ , φ the same ordertype either x <∗ y or x;y WO, any order-embedding of (x;<Q) , φ 2 into (y;<Q) is cofinal and vice versa Q either x <∗ y or x;y WO, f Q E(f ;x;y) p y q x p 6 f (q) , φ 2 8 2 ! 8 2 9 2 Q and f Q E(f ;y;x) p x q y p 6 f (q) ; 8 2 ! 8 2 9 2 1 which also is Π1. 1 Exercise 3. Show that the usual rank of trees is a Π1 rank on the set of wellfounded trees WF TrN. ⊆ We can now deduce some classical separation and reduction theorems directly 1 from the existence of Π1-ranks. Theorem 4. Let X be a Polish space and R X N be a coanalytic subset. Then there ⊆ × is a coanalytic subset R∗ R uniformising R, i.e., such that for all x X, n (x;n) R !n (x;n) R . ⊆ 2 9 2 , 9 2 ∗ 6 N R R∗ - projX(R) X Proof. Suppose R X N is Π1 and let φ: R ! be a coanalytic rank. To uni- ⊆ × 1 ! 1 formise R, for every x projX(R), we look for an n such that (x;n) R and φ(x;n) is least possible. If there2 are several such n, we then choose the smallest2 of these. That is, we set (x;n) R∗ (x;n) R & m (x;n) 6∗ (x;m)& m (x;n) <∗ (x;m) or n 6 m ; 2 , 2 8 φ 8 φ 1 which is clearly Π1. 1 Corollary 5 (K. Kuratowski, Generalised reduction for Π1). If (Cn) is a sequence of coanalytic subsets of a Polish space X, then there is a sequence (C ) of pairwise disjoint S S n∗ coanalytic sets such that C C and C = C . n∗ ⊆ n n n∗ n n 1 Proof. Set (x;n) R x Cn and let R∗ R be a Π1-uniformisation. Then 2 , 2 ⊆ Cn∗ = x X (x;n) R∗ is a reducing sequence. f 2 2 g Corollary 6 (P. S. Novikov, Generalised separation for Σ1). If (A ) is a sequence of T 1 n analytic subsets of a Polish space X with A = , then there is a sequence (B ) of T n n n Borel sets such that A B and B = . ; n ⊆ n n n ; COANALYTIC RANKS AND THE REFLECTION THEOREMS 3 Proof. Given (A ), we let C = A and find a reducing sequence C C of coan- n S Sn n T n∗ n alytic sets. Thus, C = C∼ = A = X and thus the C partition⊆ X. Since S n n∗ n n ∼ n n n∗ Cn∗ = Cm∗ , it follows that the Bn = Cn∗ are also analytic and hence Borel. ∼ m,n Theorem 7 (Boundedness for coanalytic ranks). Let X be a Polish space, C X a ⊆ coanalytic subset and φ: C !1 a coanalytic rank on C. Then of A C is an analytic subset, we have ! ⊆ sup φ(x) x A < !1: f 2 g Also, for all ξ < !1, Dξ = x C φ(x) < ξ ; and f 2 g Eξ = x C φ(x) 6 ξ f 2 g are Borel subsets of X. Proof. Note that since A C is analytic in X, the relation ⊆ x y x;y A & φ(x) < φ(y) x;y A & y ∗ x ≺ , 2 , 2 φ is analytic and wellfounded on X. It follows by the Kunen–Martin Theorem that ρ( ) < !1 and thus sup φ(x) x A < !1. ≺ S f 2 g Since Dξ = ζ<ξ Eξ, it suffices to show that Eξ is Borel for all ξ < !1. Also, if α = sup φ(x) x C , we have Eξ = Eα for all α < ξ < !1, so it suffices to consider f 2 g ξ 6 α. Now, suppose first that there is x0 C such that φ(x0) > ξ and pick such an x of minimal rank. Then, for any y X, 2 0 2 y E y C & φ(y) 6 ξ y 6∗ x x ≮∗ y; 2 ξ , 2 , φ 0 , 0 φ 1 showing that Eξ is ∆1 and thus Borel. On the other hand, if there is no such x0 6 S for ξ α, then ξ = α and Eξ = Eα = ζ<α Eζ, which, by the previous case, is a countably union of Borel sets. Exercise 8 (D. H. Blackwell). Let X be a Polish space and A;B X be analytic NN NN ⊆ subsets. Fix continuous surjections f : A and g : B and set As = f [Ns] N<N ! ! NN NN and Bs = g[Ns] for all s . For every x A B = A B, we partition into three sets as follows.2 2 ; [ ; [ × NN NN Ux = (a;b) k x Aa0:::ak Bb0:::bk ; f 2 × 9 2 n g NN NN Vx = (a;b) k x Bb0:::bk 1 Aa0:::ak ; f 2 × 9 2 − n g NN NN Cx = (a;b) k x Aa :::a Bb :::b : f 2 × 8 2 0 k \ 0 k g Clearly, Ux and Vx are open, while Cx is closed. Consider now the game in which players I and II alternate in choosing natural numbers with I beginning. I a0 a1 a2 II b b b ··· 0 1 2 ··· N N The outcome of the game is then the pair (a;b) = (a0a1 :::;b0b1 :::) N N . Finally, consider the sets 2 × A∗ = x A B I has a strategy to play in Ux Cx ; f 2 ; [ ; [ g B∗ = x A B II has a strategy to play in Vx Cx ; f 2 ; [ ; [ g 4 CHRISTIAN ROSENDAL and note that since A∗ is the projection of the Borel set (x;σ) σ is a strategy for I to play in the closed set Ux Cx = Vx ; f [ ∼ g we see that A∗ is analytic. Similarly for B∗. Show that (i) A A and B B , (ii) A B = A B and, using the determinacy of ⊆ ∗ ⊆ ∗ ∗ \ ∗ \ open games, (iii) A∗ B∗ = A B = A B. Use this to give a proof of the reduction theorem for coanalytic[ sets. ; [ ; [ 2. Reflection theorems Definition 9. Suppose X is a Polish space and Φ is a property of subsets of X. We say that Φ is Π1 on Π1 if for all Polish spaces Y and Π1 sets C Y X, the set 1 1 1 ⊆ × CΦ = y Y Φ(Cy) f 2 g 1 is Π1. 1 Theorem 10 (First reflection theorem). Suppose X is a Polish space and Φ is a Π1 on 1 1 Π1 property of subsets of X. Then for any Π1 subset C X such that Φ(C), there is a Borel subset B C satisfying Φ(B). ⊆ ⊆ Proof. Without loss of generality, we may assume that C is not itself Borel and 1 1 hence that C is not Π1 either. Fix a Π1-rank φ: C !1 and let D = (x;y) ∼ 1 ! f 2 X X y <∗ x . Since D is Π , so is the set × φ g 1 n o DΦ = x X Φ y X y <∗ x 2 f 2 φ g whereby C , DΦ. Note also that if x C, then C = y X y <∗ x , whereby ∼ 2 ∼ f 2 φ g Φ y X y <∗ x and so x DΦ.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    8 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us