1 the Halting Problem

1 the Halting Problem

Math 260B | Mathematical Logic | Scribe Notes UCSD | Spring Quarter 2012 Instructor: Sam Buss Notes by: Tomoya Sato April 11, 2012 1 The Halting Problem Is there a Turing machine such that for any Turing machine M starting with a blank tape, it can compute whether or not M eventually halts? Is there a Turing machine such that for any Turing machine M with an input w, it can compute whether or not M eventually halts? Definition 1. The Halting Problem is the set H H := fpMq : M started with a blank tape and eventually halts:g Theorem 1. The Halting Problem H is undecidable. In order to show the theorem, we first show the following. ∗ Definition 2. The M-w Halting Problem is the set H of pairs (pMq; w) ∗ H := f(pMq; w): M(w) eventually halts:g Theorem 2. The M-w Halting Problem H∗ is undecidable. Proof. (Proof by contradiction): Assume that N1 is a Turing machine that decides H∗, i.e., iff N1(pMq; w) enters state qY () M(w)# ; iff N1(pMq; w) enters state qN () M(w)" . We modify N1 to form another Turing machine N2 such that iff N2(pMq; w)" () M(w)# ; iff N2(pMq; w)# () M(w)" . Finally, let N3 be a Turing machine such that N3(pMq) = N2(pMq; pMq). Then, we can derive a contradiction as follows: 1 iff iff N3(pN3q)# () N2(pN3q; pN3q))# () N3(pN3q)". Definition 3. Let Q; R ⊆ Σ∗.A many-one reduction from Q to R is a (total) recursive function f :Σ∗ ! Σ∗ such that for any w 2 Σ∗, w 2 Q () f(w) 2 R. Theorem 3. If R is decidable, then Q is decidable. Proof. Algorithm for deciding w 2 Q is the following: Input w. Then, compute f(w) and check if f(w) 2 R. If so, go to qY ; otherwise, go to qN . In order to show the Halting Problem H is undecidable, then, it suffices to show that there is a many-one reduction from the M-w Halting Problem H∗ to the Halting Problem H. S defined as follows is the many-one reduction from H∗ to H that we want: 0 S(pMq; w) := pM q, where M 0 is a Turing machine such that M 0 starts with the black input and 1. M 0 writes w on its input tape; 2. then it runs M. (Notice that M 0 has (jwj + the number of states in M)-many states.) Many-one reductions are a special case of Turing reductions, which we will discuss in later class. 2 The Second Recursion Theorem ∗ Let f be a partial recursive function with (k+1) inputs, X; w1; : : : ; wk 2 Σ . Theorem 4. There is a Turing machine such that for all input ~w, M(~w) = f(pMq; ~w), i.e., iff M(~w)# () f(pMq; ~w)#, and if so, they give the same result. 2 Proof. Given f computed by some Turing machine M0, form g : pNq 7! 0 0 pN q such that N (~w) computes N(pNq; ~w). (Notice, we still do not need a universal Turing machine here.) Suppose that g is computed by some M1. We define h such that h(pNq; ~w) = f(g(pNq); ~w). We also suppose that h is computed by some M2. Let M3 be the Turing machine with G¨odelnumber pM3q = g(pM2q). Then, M3(~w) = M2(pM2q; ~w) = h(pM2q; ~w) = f(g(pM2q); ~w) = f(pM3q; ~w) Corollary 1. There is a Turing machine M such that M starts with a blank tape and eventually outputs pMq. Proof. Take f to be such that f(X) = X. 3.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    3 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us