Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case Studies

Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case Studies

Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case Studies Hannes Leitgeb University of Bristol February 2007 Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 1 / 22 Paradigmatic case: Kant in the Critique of Pure Reason. According to Kant’s Transcendental Doctrine of Method, philosophy cannot be developed according to the definitions-axioms-proofs scheme. This is because mathematics deals with pure intuitions, whereas philosophy deals with pure concepts (or so Kant says). However, in the meantime, mathematics has developed into a theory of abstract structures in general the progress in logic shows that the “space of concepts” has itself an intricate mathematical structure if Platonists such as G¨odel are right, there is a rational intuition of concepts!? Introduction Many philosophers still deny that mathematical methods can play a substantive role in philosophy. Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 2 / 22 However, in the meantime, mathematics has developed into a theory of abstract structures in general the progress in logic shows that the “space of concepts” has itself an intricate mathematical structure if Platonists such as G¨odel are right, there is a rational intuition of concepts!? Introduction Many philosophers still deny that mathematical methods can play a substantive role in philosophy. Paradigmatic case: Kant in the Critique of Pure Reason. According to Kant’s Transcendental Doctrine of Method, philosophy cannot be developed according to the definitions-axioms-proofs scheme. This is because mathematics deals with pure intuitions, whereas philosophy deals with pure concepts (or so Kant says). Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 2 / 22 Introduction Many philosophers still deny that mathematical methods can play a substantive role in philosophy. Paradigmatic case: Kant in the Critique of Pure Reason. According to Kant’s Transcendental Doctrine of Method, philosophy cannot be developed according to the definitions-axioms-proofs scheme. This is because mathematics deals with pure intuitions, whereas philosophy deals with pure concepts (or so Kant says). However, in the meantime, mathematics has developed into a theory of abstract structures in general the progress in logic shows that the “space of concepts” has itself an intricate mathematical structure if Platonists such as G¨odel are right, there is a rational intuition of concepts!? Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 2 / 22 The necessary bridge between philosophy and mathematics is often supplied by logic broadly understood. Plan of the talk: Examples Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs Nonmonotonic Logic and Dynamical Systems Belief Revision for Conditionals and Arrow’s Theorem Semantic Paradoxes and Probability (If time permits: Meaning Similarity and Compositionality) Claims: When philosophical theories get sufficiently complex, they are in need of mathematics. Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 3 / 22 Plan of the talk: Examples Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs Nonmonotonic Logic and Dynamical Systems Belief Revision for Conditionals and Arrow’s Theorem Semantic Paradoxes and Probability (If time permits: Meaning Similarity and Compositionality) Claims: When philosophical theories get sufficiently complex, they are in need of mathematics. The necessary bridge between philosophy and mathematics is often supplied by logic broadly understood. Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 3 / 22 (If time permits: Meaning Similarity and Compositionality) Claims: When philosophical theories get sufficiently complex, they are in need of mathematics. The necessary bridge between philosophy and mathematics is often supplied by logic broadly understood. Plan of the talk: Examples Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs Nonmonotonic Logic and Dynamical Systems Belief Revision for Conditionals and Arrow’s Theorem Semantic Paradoxes and Probability Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 3 / 22 Claims: When philosophical theories get sufficiently complex, they are in need of mathematics. The necessary bridge between philosophy and mathematics is often supplied by logic broadly understood. Plan of the talk: Examples Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs Nonmonotonic Logic and Dynamical Systems Belief Revision for Conditionals and Arrow’s Theorem Semantic Paradoxes and Probability (If time permits: Meaning Similarity and Compositionality) Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 3 / 22 B. Russell, R. Carnap: generalized abstraction; abstracting “similarity classes” from similarity relations ,→ abstraction for the empirical domain (where transitivity often fails) • hS, ∼i is a similarity structure on S :iff ∼ ⊆ S × S is reflexive and symmetric. E.g.: metric similarity (for colours,...) • hS, Pi is a property structure on S :iff ≤ P ⊆ ℘(S), ∅ ∈/ P, and for every x ∈ Srthere is an r X ∈ P, s.t. x ∈ X . E.g.: (colour) spheres '$2 r r &% Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs G. Frege, A.N. Whitehead & B. Russell: definition by logical abstraction; abstracting equivalence classes from equivalence relations Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 4 / 22 ,→ abstraction for the empirical domain (where transitivity often fails) • hS, ∼i is a similarity structure on S :iff ∼ ⊆ S × S is reflexive and symmetric. E.g.: metric similarity (for colours,...) • hS, Pi is a property structure on S :iff ≤ P ⊆ ℘(S), ∅ ∈/ P, and for every x ∈ Srthere is an r X ∈ P, s.t. x ∈ X . E.g.: (colour) spheres '$2 r r &% Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs G. Frege, A.N. Whitehead & B. Russell: definition by logical abstraction; abstracting equivalence classes from equivalence relations B. Russell, R. Carnap: generalized abstraction; abstracting “similarity classes” from similarity relations Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 4 / 22 • hS, ∼i is a similarity structure on S :iff ∼ ⊆ S × S is reflexive and symmetric. E.g.: metric similarity (for colours,...) • hS, Pi is a property structure on S :iff ≤ P ⊆ ℘(S), ∅ ∈/ P, and for every x ∈ Srthere is an r X ∈ P, s.t. x ∈ X . E.g.: (colour) spheres '$2 r r &% Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs G. Frege, A.N. Whitehead & B. Russell: definition by logical abstraction; abstracting equivalence classes from equivalence relations B. Russell, R. Carnap: generalized abstraction; abstracting “similarity classes” from similarity relations ,→ abstraction for the empirical domain (where transitivity often fails) Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 4 / 22 E.g.: metric similarity (for colours,...) • hS, Pi is a property structure on S :iff ≤ P ⊆ ℘(S), ∅ ∈/ P, and for every x ∈ Srthere is an r X ∈ P, s.t. x ∈ X . E.g.: (colour) spheres '$2 r r &% Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs G. Frege, A.N. Whitehead & B. Russell: definition by logical abstraction; abstracting equivalence classes from equivalence relations B. Russell, R. Carnap: generalized abstraction; abstracting “similarity classes” from similarity relations ,→ abstraction for the empirical domain (where transitivity often fails) • hS, ∼i is a similarity structure on S :iff ∼ ⊆ S × S is reflexive and symmetric. Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 4 / 22 • hS, Pi is a property structure on S :iff P ⊆ ℘(S), ∅ ∈/ P, and for every x ∈ S there is an X ∈ P, s.t. x ∈ X . E.g.: (colour) spheres '$2 r r &% Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs G. Frege, A.N. Whitehead & B. Russell: definition by logical abstraction; abstracting equivalence classes from equivalence relations B. Russell, R. Carnap: generalized abstraction; abstracting “similarity classes” from similarity relations ,→ abstraction for the empirical domain (where transitivity often fails) • hS, ∼i is a similarity structure on S :iff ∼ ⊆ S × S is reflexive and symmetric. E.g.: metric similarity (for colours,...) ≤ r r Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 4 / 22 ≤ r r E.g.: (colour) spheres '$2 r r &% Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs G. Frege, A.N. Whitehead & B. Russell: definition by logical abstraction; abstracting equivalence classes from equivalence relations B. Russell, R. Carnap: generalized abstraction; abstracting “similarity classes” from similarity relations ,→ abstraction for the empirical domain (where transitivity often fails) • hS, ∼i is a similarity structure on S :iff ∼ ⊆ S × S is reflexive and symmetric. E.g.: metric similarity (for colours,...) • hS, Pi is a property structure on S :iff P ⊆ ℘(S), ∅ ∈/ P, and for every x ∈ S there is an X ∈ P, s.t. x ∈ X . Hannes Leitgeb (University of Bristol) Applications of Mathematics in Philosophy: Four Case StudiesFebruary 2007 4 / 22 ≤ r r Similarity, Properties, and Hypergraphs G. Frege, A.N. Whitehead & B. Russell: definition by logical abstraction;

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    125 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us