Handout from Today's Lecture

Handout from Today's Lecture

MA532 Lecture Timothy Kohl Boston University April 23, 2020 Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 1 / 26 Cardinal Arithmetic Recall that one may define addition and multiplication of ordinals α = ot(A, A) β = ot(B, B ) α + β and α · β by constructing order relations on A ∪ B and B × A. For cardinal numbers the foundations are somewhat similar, but also somewhat simpler since one need not refer to orderings. Definition For sets A, B where |A| = α and |B| = β then α + β = |(A × {0}) ∪ (B × {1})|. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 2 / 26 The curious part of the definition is the two sets A × {0} and B × {1} which can be viewed as subsets of the direct product (A ∪ B) × {0, 1} which basically allows us to add |A| and |B|, in particular since, in the usual formula for the size of the union of two sets |A ∪ B| = |A| + |B| − |A ∩ B| which in this case is bypassed since, by construction, (A × {0}) ∩ (B × {1})= ∅ regardless of the nature of A ∩ B. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 3 / 26 Definition For sets A, B where |A| = α and |B| = β then α · β = |A × B|. One immediate consequence of these definitions is the following. Proposition If m, n are finite ordinals, then as cardinals one has |m| + |n| = |m + n|, (where the addition on the right is ordinal addition in ω) meaning that ordinal addition and cardinal addition agree. Proof. The simplest proof of this is to define a bijection f : (m × {0}) ∪ (n × {1}) → m + n by f (hr, 0i)= r for r ∈ m and f (hs, 1i)= m + s for s ∈ n. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 4 / 26 And in a similar fashion, one has the relatively obvious fact: Proposition If m, n are finite ordinals, then as cardinals |m| · |n| = |m · n|, where the multiplication on the right is ordinal multiplication in ω. Proof. Exercise. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 5 / 26 The addition and multiplication of cardinals differs from that ordinals. Proposition For cardinal numbers α,β, and γ: (a) α + β = β + α (b) α +0= α (c) (α + β)+ γ = α + (β + γ) (d) α · 0 = 0 (e) α · 1= α (f) α · 2= α + α (and similarly for α · n) (g) (α · β) = (β · α) (h) (α · β) · γ = α · (β · γ) (i) α · (β + γ)= α · β + α · γ Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 6 / 26 Proof. (a) There is a fairly obvious bijection f : (A × {0}) ∪ (B × {1}) → (B × {0}) × (A × {1}), namely ha, 0i 7→ ha, 1i and hb, 1i 7→ hb, 0i, and so |A| + |B| =c |B| + |A| (b) As ∅ × {1} = ∅ then (A × {0}) ∪ (∅ × {1}) = (A × {0}) ergo |A| + |∅| = |A|. (c) [Exercise] (d) For any set A we have A × ∅ = ∅ so |A| · |∅| = |∅|. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 7 / 26 The remaining statements are proved similarly. Proof. (e) There is a bijection A × 1= A × {0}→ A given by ha, 0i 7→ a which implies |A| · |1| = |A|. (f) As 2= {0, 1} there is yet another obvious bijection (A × {0}) ∪ (A × {1}) → A × 2= A × {0, 1} since, in fact, (A × {0}) ∪ (A × {1})= A × {0, 1} (g,h,i) Exercises. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 8 / 26 For the definition of ordinal exponentiation, we recall that for sets A and B, the functions f : B → A is denoted B A. Definition If α, β are cardinal numbers, then αβ denotes the unique cardinal γ such that, for sets A and B where |A| = α and |B| = β then γ = |B A|. For finite sets, for example, 32, a function f : 3 → 2 is a mapping from 3= {0, 1, 2} to 2= {0, 1}, i.e. f (0) = 0 or 1,f (1) = 0 or 1,f (2) = 0 or 1, ergo |32| = 23 = 8, where, not coincidentally |32| =c |P(3)|. And indeed, 2|A| = |P(A)| for any cardinality |A|. And of course, for finite cardinals m, n in general, the set nm has mn elements, i.e. cardinal exponentiation and ordinal exponentiation (in ω) are the same thing. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 9 / 26 We observe a number of facts about the exponentiation of cardinal numbers. Proposition For cardinals α, β, and γ: (a) α0 = 1 (b) α1 = α (c) α2 = α · α (d) αn = αn−1 · α for n a finite cardinal (e) if β 6= 0, 0β = 0 (f) 1β = 1 (g) αβ+γ = αβ · αγ (h) αβ·γ = (αβ)γ (i) (α · β)γ = αβ · βγ Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 10 / 26 Proof. (a) This is somewhat curious statement since α0 represents the cardinality of ∅α, the totality of functions from ∅ to α, but this consists of the empty set so it equals {∅} = {0} = 1. (b) Each function in 1α has domain consisting of a single element, and so the number of functions is in bijective correspondence with the cardinality of α, ergo α1 = α. (c,d) Exercises. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 11 / 26 Here are the proofs of the remaining statements. Proof. (e) In contrast with α0, for 0β one is looking at the set of function B → ∅ for some set B with α = |B| then we must realize that no function with a non-empty domain can have range ∅. (f) Exercise (g) For sets A, B, C, with cardinal numbers α, β and γ one compares functions (B × {0}) ∪ (C × {1}) → A with the direct product (B A) × (C A) and realize that since (B × {0}) ∩ (C × {1})= ∅ any f : B × {0}→ A and g : C × {1}→ A are ’independent’ and so determine a unique function hf , gi∈ (B A) × (C A). (h,i) Exercises. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 12 / 26 Cofinality For the definition we give next, we need to give a definition of limit. Definition If α> 0 is a limit ordinal, and hγζ | ζ < αi be a non-decreasing sequence of ordinals (i.e. ζ < η implies γζ ≤ γη) then the limit of the sequence lim γζ = sup{γζ | ζ < α} ζ→α and a sequence of ordinals hγα | α ∈ Oni is normal if it is increasing and continuous, i.e. for every limit ordinal α, γα = lim γζ ζ→α Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 13 / 26 Definition If α> 0 is a limit ordinal, we say that an increasing sequence hαζ | ζ < βi, β a limit ordinal, is cofinal in α if lim αζ = α. ζ→β Similarly, A ⊆ α is a cofinal in α if supA = α. If α is an infinite limit ordinal, the confinality of α is cf (α) = the least limit ordinal β such that there is an increasing sequence hαζ | ζ < βi with lim αζ = α ζ→β Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 14 / 26 A slightly easier definition perhaps is this: Definition Let α, β be ordinals and let f : α → β be a function, f is cofinal (or α cofinally (in)to β) if for all γ < β, there exists δ < α such that γ ≤ f (δ). Let β ∈ On then the confinality of β, denoted cf (β), is the minimal α such that there is a cofinal function from α to β. So cf (β) ≤ β and is a cardinal for any β, and if β is a successor ordinal (i.e. not a limit ordinal) then cf (β) = 1 via the function f (0) = S β. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 15 / 26 A more familiar way of viewing cofinality is from the theory of sequences from real analysis/calculus. In particular, if {an} is a sequence, and if {kn} is defined as a sequence of indices such that lim kn = ∞ then {akn } is a subsequence of {an}. n→∞ One of the canonical properties of convergent sequences {an} is that if L = lim an (finite) then for any subsequence {akn } one has lim akn = L n→∞ n→∞ as well. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 16 / 26 1 1 For example, given the sequence, { 2n } we have that { 4n } is a subsequence, and both tend to zero as n →∞. Although it’s not essential here, we observe that there exists sequences {an} with subsequences {bn} and {cn} such that lim bn = L1 and n→∞ lim cn = L2 (where L1 and L2 are finite) but where L1 6= L2. n→∞ In this situation we conclude that lim an does not exist, so the n→∞ convergence of the sequence implying the convergence of all subsequences is a pretty stringent condition. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 17 / 26 And, in terms of sets, the cofinality can be be viewed as a kind of ’density’ 1 1 of one in the other, for example with the { 2n } and { 4n } sequences earlier, as sets 1 1 1 1 { } = { , , ,... } 4n 4 16 64 is cofinal in 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 { } = { , , , , , , ,... } 2n 2 4 8 16 32 64 128 1 1 since every other term of { 2n } is one of the elements of { 4n }. Timothy Kohl (Boston University) MA532 Lecture April 23, 2020 18 / 26 So for a given ordinal α the cofinality is basically the order type of any index set of a sequence whose terms comprise a cofinal set.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    26 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us