Chapter 6: Cardinal Numbers and the Axiom of Choice Equinumerosity March 18 & 20, 2014

Chapter 6: Cardinal Numbers and the Axiom of Choice Equinumerosity March 18 & 20, 2014

Elements of Set Theory Chapter 6: Cardinal Numbers and The Axiom of Choice Equinumerosity March 18 & 20, 2014 Lecturer: Fan Yang 1/28 2/28 What is the size of a set? X = f , , , g Y = f , , , , g ! = f0; 1; 2; 3; 4;::: g Do A and B have the same size? Does A have more elements than B? Are there exactly as many houses as people? Y has more elements than X. Yes, since there are 5 houses and 5 people. The infinite set ! has more elements than the finite sets X and Y . Yes, since there is a one-to-one correspondence between the two Do ! and Z have the same size? What about Q and Z? sets. 0 1 2 3 ! Definition 6.1 -3 -2 -1 0 1 2 3 Z A set A is said to be equinumerous or equipotent to a set B (written 3 1 11 − 2 2 4 A ≈ B) iff there is a bijection from A onto B. -3 -2 -1 0 1 2 3 Q A bijection from A onto B is also called a one-to-one correspondence Given two infinite sets A and B, how to compare their sizes? between sets A and B. 3/28 4/28 Example 6.1: Let A = fa; b; c; dg and B = fa; b; cg. Then A 6≈ B, since there is no bijection from A onto B. In general, for any two finite sets X and Y , if Y ⊂ X, then X 6≈ Y . Consider the following infinite sets. Clearly, Even ⊂ !. ! = f0; 1; 2; 3; 4; 5; 6;::: g, Even = f0; 2; 4; 6; 8; 10; 12;::: g = f2n j n 2 !g. Example 6.2: ! ≈ Even. Are there exactly as many knives as forks? Proof. The function f : ! ! Even defined by taking Yes, as there is a one-to-one correspondence between knives and forks. f (n) = 2n is a bijection. Indeed, f is injective, since n 6= m =) 2n 6= 2m. f is surjective, since for all m 2 Even, m = 2n for some n 2 !, and f (n) = 2n = m. 5/28 6/28 Example 6.3: [Galileo] Similarly, ! ≈ Sq, where ! = f0; 1; 2; 3; 4; 5;::: g, Example 6.5: ! × ! ≈ !. Sq = f0; 1; 4; 9; 16; 25;::: g = fn2 j n 2 !g. Proof. The function f : ! × ! ! ! defined as 1 f (m; n) = [(m + n)2 + 3m + n] since there is a bijection f : ! ! Sq defined as f (n) = n2. 2 is a bijection. Example 6.4: ! ≈ ! n f0g, since the function f : ! ! ! n f0g defined as ! f (n) = n+ is a bijection. 10 0 1 2 3 4 ! 11 6 12 1 2 3 4 ! n f0g 3 7 Remark: For infinite sets A; B, 1 4 8 13 A ⊂ B 6=) A 6≈ B ! 0 2 5 9 14 ! 7/28 8/28 Example 6.6: Q ≈ !. Example 6.7: (0; 1) ≈ R, where (0; 1) = fx 2 R j 0 < x < 1g. Proof. In the following picture, we specify a bijection f : ! ! Q. 3 3 3 3 3 1 2 3 4 5 Proof. By picture. Here (0; 1) has been bent into a semicircle with center P. Each point in (0; 1) is paired with its projection (from P) on [10] 2 2 2 [9] 2 2 the real line. 1 2 3 4 5 [1] 1 1 [2] 1 [8] 1 1 1 2 3 4 5 0 1 [0] 0 0 0 0 0 1 2 3 4 5 :::::: x [4] 1 1 [3] 1 [7] 1 1 − 1 − 2 − 3 − 4 − 5 [5] 2 2 2 [6] 2 2 − 1 − 2 − 3 − 4 − 5 r R 3 3 3 3 3 − 1 − 2 − 3 − 4 − 5 9/28 10/28 Recall : for any sets X and Y , An alternative proof: Claim: the mapping f :(0; 1) ! defined by R X putting Y = ff : X ! Y j f is a functiong: 1 1 f (x) = − x 1 − x Example 6.8: For any set A, we have }A ≈ A2. is a bijection. 1 1 1 1 For any a; b 2 (0; 1), if f (a) = f (b), namely, if a − 1−a = b − 1−b , then Proof. Define a function H : }A ! A2 by taking (b − a) 1 + 1 = 0 thereby a = b. Hence f is injective. ab (1−a)(1−b) H(B) = fB; For any r 2 , there is x = p 2 2 (0; 1) such that where f : A ! f0; 1g is the characteristic function of B defined as R r 2 B r+ 4+r +2 ( 1 if x 2 B; 1 1 1 1 f (x) = f (x ) = − = − 2 B r x 1 − x x 1 − x 0 if x 2 A n B: r p r r p r r + 4 + r 2 − 2 r + 4 + r 2 + 2 Claim: H is a bijection. = · p 2 r + 4 + r 2 Indeed, H is injective, since for any B; C ⊆ A, p 2 2 (r + 4 + r 2) − 2 H(B) = H(C) =) fB = fC =) 8x 2 A(fB(x) = fC(x)) = p = r: 2(r + 4 + r 2) =) 8x 2 A(x 2 B $ x 2 C) =) B = C; A Hence f is surjective. H is surjective, since for any function g 2 2, there is B = fx 2 A j g(x) = 1g ⊆ A such that H(B) = fB = g. 11/28 12/28 Theorem 6B (Cantor 1873) (a) The set ! is not equinumerous to the set R of real numbers. (b) No set is equinumerous to its power set. Theorem 6A Proof. (a) [Diagonal argument] Given any map f : ! ! R. We show For any sets A; B and C: that there exists z 2 R such that z 2= ran f . (a) A ≈ A. f (0) = 236: 0012 0 1 2 ::: (b) If A ≈ B, then B ≈ A. f (1) = −7: 73 374 7 4 ::: (c) If A ≈ B and B ≈ C, then A ≈ C. f (2) = 3: 1 41 15 5 ::: Proof. Exercise. f (3) = 0: 5 2 46 6 ::: . That is, ≈ is an “equivalence relation” on the class of all sets. The integer part of z is 0, and the (n + 1)st decimal place of z is 3 unless the (n + 1)st decimal place of f (n) is 3, in which case the (n + 1)st decimal place of z is 4. For example, in the case shown, z = 0:3433 ::: Clearly, z 6= f (n) for all n, as it differs from f (n) in the (n + 1)st decimal place. Hence z 2= ran f . 13/28 14/28 (b) Suppose g : A ! }A is surjective. Let B = fx 2 A j x 2= g(x)g: Since B 2 }A and g is surjective, there exists x0 2 A such that g(x0) = B: But then, by the definition of B, Finite Sets x0 2 B () x0 2= g(x0) = B; which is a contradiction. Hence there is no surjection from A onto }A, thus A 6≈ }A. Remark: We will soon be able to prove R ≈ }!. R has smaller size than }R, which has smaller size than }}R, etc. 15/28 16/28 Definition 6.2 3 4 5 2 A set is finite iff it is equinumerous to some natural number. Otherwise it is infinite. 1 That is, for any set A: 0 A is finite iff 9n 2 !(A ≈ n) A is infinite iff 8n 2 !(A 6≈ n) Example 6.9: The set A = fa0; a1; a2; a3g is finite, since A ≈ 4 via the bijection f : 4 ! A defined as: f (n) = an. 4 = f0; 1; 2; 3g A = fa0; a1; a2; a3g Example 6.10: Any finite set A is not equinumerous to an infinite set B. There are finitely many forks in the picture. Why? Proof. Suppose A ≈ B. As A is finite, A ≈ n for some n 2 !. From the Because there are exactly6 forks. This, in turn, is because there is a transitivity of ≈, it follows that B ≈ n, contradicting B being infinite. one-to-one correspondence between the natural number Next, we want to check that each finite set A is equinumerous to a 6 = f0; 1; 2; 3; 4; 5g and the set F of forks, or in other words, 6 ≈ F. unique natural number n. This requires the Pigeonhole Principle. 17/28 18/28 Proof. (of Pigeonhole Principle) We shall show that for any n 2 !, if f : n ! n Pigeonhole Principle: is a one-to-one function, then ran f = n (not a proper subset of n), namely, that the set T is inductive: If n items are put into m pigeonholes with n > m, T = fn 2 ! j ran f = n for any one-to-one function f : n ! ng: then at least one pigeon- Base case: 0 2 T , since the only function f : 0 ! 0 is the empty function hole must contain more f = ;, and ran ; = ;. than one item. Inductive step: Assume k 2 T and f : k + ! k + is a one-to-one function. We + + Here n = 10 and m = 9. show that ran f = k . Note that f k is a one-to-one function from k into k . Case 1: ran (f k) ⊆ k. Then f k : k ! k is a one-to-one function, as + + f : k ! k is 1-1. Thus, the assumption k 2 T implies ran f k = k. Pigeonhole Princinple Moreover, since f is 1-1, we must have f (k) = k.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    7 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us