Continuous First-Order Logic

Continuous First-Order Logic

Continuous First-Order Logic Wesley Calvert Calcutta Logic Circle 4 September 2011 Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 1 / 45 Definition A first-order theory T is said to be stable iff there are less than the maximum possible number of types over T , up to equivalence. Theorem (Shelah's Main Gap Theorem) If T is a first-order theory and is stable and . , then the class of models looks like . Otherwise, there's no hope. Model-Theoretic Beginnings Problem Given a theory T , describe the structure of models of T . Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 2 / 45 Theorem (Shelah's Main Gap Theorem) If T is a first-order theory and is stable and . , then the class of models looks like . Otherwise, there's no hope. Model-Theoretic Beginnings Problem Given a theory T , describe the structure of models of T . Definition A first-order theory T is said to be stable iff there are less than the maximum possible number of types over T , up to equivalence. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 2 / 45 Model-Theoretic Beginnings Problem Given a theory T , describe the structure of models of T . Definition A first-order theory T is said to be stable iff there are less than the maximum possible number of types over T , up to equivalence. Theorem (Shelah's Main Gap Theorem) If T is a first-order theory and is stable and . , then the class of models looks like . Otherwise, there's no hope. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 2 / 45 Model-Theoretic Beginnings Example Let T be the theory of vector spaces over some infinite field. Then for each uncountable cardinal κ, there is exactly one model of T , up to isomorphism, with cardinality κ. Moreover, there are only countably many countable models, and we know what they are. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 3 / 45 1 For all x 2 V , we have jxj ≥ 0. 2 If jxj = 0, then x = 0. 3 For all x 2 V and all λ 2 R we have jλxj = jλj · jxj. 4 For all x; y 2 V , we have jx + yj ≤ jxj + jyj. Model-Theoretic Beginnings Definition Let V be a vector space over R.A norm on V is a function j · j : V ! R satisfying the following: Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 4 / 45 2 If jxj = 0, then x = 0. 3 For all x 2 V and all λ 2 R we have jλxj = jλj · jxj. 4 For all x; y 2 V , we have jx + yj ≤ jxj + jyj. Model-Theoretic Beginnings Definition Let V be a vector space over R.A norm on V is a function j · j : V ! R satisfying the following: 1 For all x 2 V , we have jxj ≥ 0. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 4 / 45 3 For all x 2 V and all λ 2 R we have jλxj = jλj · jxj. 4 For all x; y 2 V , we have jx + yj ≤ jxj + jyj. Model-Theoretic Beginnings Definition Let V be a vector space over R.A norm on V is a function j · j : V ! R satisfying the following: 1 For all x 2 V , we have jxj ≥ 0. 2 If jxj = 0, then x = 0. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 4 / 45 4 For all x; y 2 V , we have jx + yj ≤ jxj + jyj. Model-Theoretic Beginnings Definition Let V be a vector space over R.A norm on V is a function j · j : V ! R satisfying the following: 1 For all x 2 V , we have jxj ≥ 0. 2 If jxj = 0, then x = 0. 3 For all x 2 V and all λ 2 R we have jλxj = jλj · jxj. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 4 / 45 Model-Theoretic Beginnings Definition Let V be a vector space over R.A norm on V is a function j · j : V ! R satisfying the following: 1 For all x 2 V , we have jxj ≥ 0. 2 If jxj = 0, then x = 0. 3 For all x 2 V and all λ 2 R we have jλxj = jλj · jxj. 4 For all x; y 2 V , we have jx + yj ≤ jxj + jyj. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 4 / 45 Example Let (V ; j · j) be a normed vector space over R.Then define an equivalence relation x ∼ y iff jxj = jyj, and order the classes by x∼ < y∼ iff jxj < jyj. Thus, (V ; j · j) is unstable, and the class of models of its first-order theory is completely intractable. Problem Then how can we possibly think about Hilbert Spaces? Model-Theoretic Beginnings Proposition A first-order theory is said to be stable iff there is no definable infinite linear ordering in any model. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 5 / 45 Then define an equivalence relation x ∼ y iff jxj = jyj, and order the classes by x∼ < y∼ iff jxj < jyj. Thus, (V ; j · j) is unstable, and the class of models of its first-order theory is completely intractable. Problem Then how can we possibly think about Hilbert Spaces? Model-Theoretic Beginnings Proposition A first-order theory is said to be stable iff there is no definable infinite linear ordering in any model. Example Let (V ; j · j) be a normed vector space over R. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 5 / 45 Thus, (V ; j · j) is unstable, and the class of models of its first-order theory is completely intractable. Problem Then how can we possibly think about Hilbert Spaces? Model-Theoretic Beginnings Proposition A first-order theory is said to be stable iff there is no definable infinite linear ordering in any model. Example Let (V ; j · j) be a normed vector space over R.Then define an equivalence relation x ∼ y iff jxj = jyj, and order the classes by x∼ < y∼ iff jxj < jyj. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 5 / 45 Problem Then how can we possibly think about Hilbert Spaces? Model-Theoretic Beginnings Proposition A first-order theory is said to be stable iff there is no definable infinite linear ordering in any model. Example Let (V ; j · j) be a normed vector space over R.Then define an equivalence relation x ∼ y iff jxj = jyj, and order the classes by x∼ < y∼ iff jxj < jyj. Thus, (V ; j · j) is unstable, and the class of models of its first-order theory is completely intractable. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 5 / 45 Model-Theoretic Beginnings Proposition A first-order theory is said to be stable iff there is no definable infinite linear ordering in any model. Example Let (V ; j · j) be a normed vector space over R.Then define an equivalence relation x ∼ y iff jxj = jyj, and order the classes by x∼ < y∼ iff jxj < jyj. Thus, (V ; j · j) is unstable, and the class of models of its first-order theory is completely intractable. Problem Then how can we possibly think about Hilbert Spaces? Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 5 / 45 Example Let p > 0, and define 1 Z p p jjf jjp := jf j : p We define L (R) to be the set of all functions f : R ! R such that jjf jjp < 1, with pointwise addition and scaling and the norm jj · jjp. Each p space L (R) is a Banach space. Model-Theoretic Beginnings Definition A Banach Space is a normed vector space with the property that every Cauchy sequence converges to a point of the space (i.e. a complete normed vector space). Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 6 / 45 p We define L (R) to be the set of all functions f : R ! R such that jjf jjp < 1, with pointwise addition and scaling and the norm jj · jjp. Each p space L (R) is a Banach space. Model-Theoretic Beginnings Definition A Banach Space is a normed vector space with the property that every Cauchy sequence converges to a point of the space (i.e. a complete normed vector space). Example Let p > 0, and define 1 Z p p jjf jjp := jf j : Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 6 / 45 Model-Theoretic Beginnings Definition A Banach Space is a normed vector space with the property that every Cauchy sequence converges to a point of the space (i.e. a complete normed vector space). Example Let p > 0, and define 1 Z p p jjf jjp := jf j : p We define L (R) to be the set of all functions f : R ! R such that jjf jjp < 1, with pointwise addition and scaling and the norm jj · jjp. Each p space L (R) is a Banach space. Wesley Calvert (SIU / IMSc) Continuous First-Order Logic 4 September 2011 6 / 45 1 For all x; y; z 2 V and all a; b 2 R, we have hax + by; zi = ahx; zi + bhy; zi 2 For all x; y 2 V , we have hx; yi = hy; xi 3 For all x 2 V , we have hx; xi ≥ 0, with equality holding if and only if x = 0.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    128 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us