Pragmatic Encroachment Jeremy Fantl and Matthew Mcgrath in His

Pragmatic Encroachment Jeremy Fantl and Matthew Mcgrath in His

View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Missouri: MOspace Pragmatic Encroachment Jeremy Fantl and Matthew McGrath In his classic (1953) article, Richard Rudner claims that in accepting a hypothesis the scientist must make the decision that the evidence is sufficiently strong or that the probability is sufficiently high to warrant the acceptance of the hypothesis. Obviously, our decision regarding the evidence and respecting how strong is ‘strong enough’, is going to be a function of the importance , in the typically ethical sense, of making a mistake in accepting or rejecting the hypothesis… How sure we need to be before we accept a hypothesis will depend on how serious a mistake would be . (2, emphasis Rudner’s) According to Rudner, an adequate account of the conditions of warranted hypothesis acceptance must include reference to an ethical or more broadly a pragmatic factor. Rudner explicitly confines his discussion to the evidence or probability needed to be warranted in accepting a hypothesis, where acceptance for him seems to be subject to voluntary control, at least in certain cases: we decide the evidence is sufficiently strong. But in the past decade a number of philosophers have offered views similar to Rudner’s about a broader range of epistemic concepts. For example, regarding knowledge, Jeremy Fantl and Matthew McGrath ((2002) and (2007)), John Hawthorne (2004), and Jason Stanley (2005) 1 have recommended views according to which, whether a subject knows something to be the case depends on their practical situation. This sort of conclusion shouldn’t strike us as immediately implausible. After all, there are widely acknowledged links between the practical and the epistemic. What you should do in a 1 See also Hawthorne and Stanley’s co-authored (forthcoming). certain choice situation is widely acknowledged to be determined not merely by how good or preferred certain possible outcomes of your acts would be but how probable these outcomes are given that you act in certain ways. Or consider again the importance of not being wrong. This seems obviously relevant to whether you should inquire further into whether p and to whether your evidence is strong enough to justify you in ignoring the chance that p is false. If your practical situation can be relevant to these matters, it might not seem to be a huge step to think it can be relevant to whether you know . Some of our intuitions about specific cases seem to support the claim that knowledge can depend on practical factors Consider DeRose’s famous (1992) “Bank Cases”: Bank Case A (Low Stakes). My wife and I are driving home on a Friday afternoon. We plan to stop at the bank on the way home to deposit our paychecks. But as we drive past the bank, we notice that the lines inside are very long, as they often are on Friday afternoons. Although we generally like to deposit our paychecks as soon as possible, it is not especially important in this case that they be deposited right away, so I suggest that we drive straight home and deposit our paychecks on Saturday morning. My wife says, “Maybe the bank won’t be open tomorrow. Lots of banks are closed on Saturdays.” I reply, “No, I know it’ll be open. I was just there two weeks ago on Saturday. It’s open until noon.” Bank Case B (High Stakes). My wife and I drive past the bank on a Friday afternoon, as in Case A, and notice the long lines. I again suggest that we deposit our paychecks on Saturday morning, explaining that I was at the bank on Saturday morning only two weeks ago and discovered that it was open until noon. But in this case, we have just written a very large and important check. If our paychecks are not deposited into our checking account before Monday morning, the important check we wrote will bounce, leaving us in a very bad situation. And, of course, the bank is not open on Sunday. My wife reminds me of these facts. She then says, “Banks do change their hours. Do you know the bank will be open tomorrow?” Remaining as confident as I was before that the bank will be open then, still, I reply, “Well, no. I’d better go in and make sure.” (913) It looks like Keith speaks truly in Case A in attributing knowledge to himself that the bank will be open tomorrow, while he also speaks truly in Case B in denying himself knowledge. The only thing that changes in the two cases is how important it is for Keith to be right about whether the bank will be open tomorrow. Therefore, it looks like how important it is for Keith to be right about whether the bank will be open tomorrow is relevant to whether Keith knows that the bank will be open tomorrow. And relevant in a clear way: holding fixed Keith’s evidence concerning whether the bank will be open tomorrow, whether he knows it will be open varies with variations in how important it is for him to be right about this. But here we find some odd consequences. If this is the proper lesson to draw from the Bank Cases, it would appear to follow that two subjects can have the same evidence concerning whether the bank will be open tomorrow, even though one of them knows it’ll open tomorrow and the other doesn’t. And this will be just because one subject believes the bank will be open tomorrow and the other doesn’t. 2 Nor because the bank will be open tomorrow and false in the other, nor because one subject is Gettiered and the other not. What makes the difference in knowledge has nothing to do with these traditional factors. In fact, one subject might have more evidence than another that the bank will be open tomorrow – be better informed, have done more checking, etc. – but because much more is at stake for the more well-informed subject, the more well-informed subject can fail to know that the bank will be open tomorrow while the less- informed subject knows that the bank will be open tomorrow. All this is hard to swallow. DeRose himself draws a very different moral from the cases. He grants that Keith speaks truly in Case A when he says “I know it’ll be open” and he also speaks truly in Case B when he responds “no” to the question, “Do you know that the bank will be open tomorrow?” But he 2 Kent Bach questions whether Keith is allowed to stipulate that he remain as confident even once the stakes change, and also questions whether, even if he retains the same degree of belief – the same credence – between the two cases, his credence remains sufficient for outright belief. His worries are shared by Jennifer Nagel, though she ends up granting the possibility that Keith retains belief between the cases. If one thinks Keith can’t sincerely say “I better go in and make sure” if he has a belief that the bank will be open tomorrow, then we can alter the case by stipulating that Keith says, “I know it’s open tomorrow.” We can further emend the case by having Keith’s wife say, “No you don’t. This is important, Keith. You need to go in and make sure they’re open tomorrow.” The question would then be whether what Keith said is false. We see no great gulf between the original case B and this altered one. insists that it does not follow that the bank cases show that pragmatic factors can make a difference to knowledge. Why not? DeRose’s answer, to put it roughly, is that Keith’s pragmatic situation affects what he means by ‘know’ but makes no difference to whether he knows. Put more precisely, his answer has two parts. First, there is a contextualist claim: which epistemic relation Keith’s use of ‘know’ picks out varies with his pragmatic situation, and so varies across the bank cases. If the epistemic relations picked out vary with the pragmatic situation – the higher the stakes, roughly, the more demanding the epistemic relation picked out – what Keith says in case A might be true while what he said in case B might be false. That is the first part – the claim that pragmatic factors matter to the content of knowledge-attributions. The second part is the denial that they matter to knowledge. Or to put it more precisely: for each epistemic relation K that can be picked out by ‘know’ in some context, pragmatic factors make no difference to whether you stand in K to a proposition. If this is true of all such relations, then the sentence ‘Pragmatic factors make no difference to whether one knows’ comes out invariantly true. What is important for our purposes is that the contextualist finds a way to salvage the intuitions in the cases while avoiding some of the problematic consequences of letting knowledge involve the subject’s practical situation. Thus, an important motivation for contextualism, it might be thought, is the avoidance of those problematic consequences. 3 But contextualism comes with problems of its own; for one thing, the problematic consequences remain, but bumped up a level. The contextualist, it seems, must grant that two subjects might have the same evidence that the bank will be open tomorrow, but one could truly self-attribute knowledge while the other truly self-denies knowledge. One subject could have 3 This point is emphasized by DeRose in his (forthcoming).

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    19 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us