The Psychology of Existential Risk: Moral Judgments About Human Extinction

The Psychology of Existential Risk: Moral Judgments About Human Extinction

ORE Open Research Exeter TITLE The psychology of existential risk: Moral judgments about human extinction AUTHORS Schubert, S; Caviola, L; Faber, N JOURNAL Scientific Reports DEPOSITED IN ORE 09 September 2019 This version available at http://hdl.handle.net/10871/38609 COPYRIGHT AND REUSE Open Research Exeter makes this work available in accordance with publisher policies. A NOTE ON VERSIONS The version presented here may differ from the published version. If citing, you are advised to consult the published version for pagination, volume/issue and date of publication www.nature.com/scientificreports OPEN The Psychology of Existential Risk: Moral Judgments about Human Received: 4 June 2019 Extinction Accepted: 4 September 2019 Published: xx xx xxxx Stefan Schubert 1, Lucius Caviola1 & Nadira S. Faber 1,2,3 The 21st century will likely see growing risks of human extinction, but currently, relatively small resources are invested in reducing such existential risks. Using three samples (UK general public, US general public, and UK students; total N = 2,507), we study how laypeople reason about human extinction. We fnd that people think that human extinction needs to be prevented. Strikingly, however, they do not think that an extinction catastrophe would be uniquely bad relative to near-extinction catastrophes, which allow for recovery. More people fnd extinction uniquely bad when (a) asked to consider the extinction of an animal species rather than humans, (b) asked to consider a case where human extinction is associated with less direct harm, and (c) they are explicitly prompted to consider long-term consequences of the catastrophes. We conclude that an important reason why people do not fnd extinction uniquely bad is that they focus on the immediate death and sufering that the catastrophes cause for fellow humans, rather than on the long-term consequences. Finally, we fnd that (d) laypeople—in line with prominent philosophical arguments—think that the quality of the future is relevant: they do fnd extinction uniquely bad when this means forgoing a utopian future. Te ever-increasing powers of technology can be used for good and ill. In the 21st century, technological advances will likely yield great benefts to humanity, but experts warn that they will also lead to growing risks of human extinction1–4. Te risks stem both from existing technologies such as nuclear weapons, as well as emerging tech- nologies such as synthetic biology and artifcial intelligence5. A small but growing number of research institutes, such as the University of Oxford’s Future of Humanity Institute and the University of Cambridge’s Centre for the Study of Existential Risk, are studying these risks and how to mitigate them. Yet besides them, relatively small resources are explicitly devoted to reducing these risks. Here, we study the general public’s views of the badness of human extinction. We hypothesize that most people judge human extinction to be bad. But how bad do they fnd it? And why do they fnd it bad? Besides being highly policy-relevant, these questions are central for humanity’s understanding of itself and its place in nature. Human extinction is a pervasive theme in myths and religious writings6–10. One view is that human extinction is bad primarily because it would harm many concrete individuals: it would mean the death of all currently living people. On this view, human extinction is a very bad event, but it is not much worse than catastrophes that kill nearly all currently living people—since the diference in terms of numbers of deaths would be relatively small. Another view is that the human extinction is bad primarily because it would mean that the human species would go extinct and that humanity’s future would be lost forever. On this view, human extinction is uniquely bad: much worse even than catastrophes killing nearly everyone, since we could recover from them and re-build civilization. Whether extinction is uniquely bad or not depends on which of these considerations is the stronger: the immediate harm, or the long-term consequences. Here is one way to pit these considerations against each other. Consider three outcomes: no catastrophe, a catastrophe killing 80% (near-extinction), and a catastrophe killing 100% (extinction). According to both con- siderations, no catastrophe is the best outcome, and extinction the worst outcome. But they come apart regarding the relative diferences between the three outcomes. If the immediate harm is the more important consideration, 1Department of Experimental Psychology, University of Oxford, New Radcliffe House, Radcliffe Observatory Quarter, Woodstock Road, OX2 6GG, Oxford, United Kingdom. 2Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, University of Oxford, 16-17 St Ebbes St, Oxford, OX1 1PT, United Kingdom. 3College of Life and Environmental Sciences, University of Exeter, Washington Singer Building, Exeter, EX4 4QG, United Kingdom. Stefan Schubert and Lucius Caviola contributed equally. Correspondence and requests for materials should be addressed to S.S. (email: stefan. [email protected]) SCIENTIFIC REPORTS | (2019) 9:15100 | https://doi.org/10.1038/s41598-019-50145-9 1 www.nature.com/scientificreports/ www.nature.com/scientificreports then the frst diference, between no catastrophe and near-extinction, is greater than the second diference, between near-extinction and extinction. Tat is because the frst diference is greater in terms of numbers of harmed individuals. On the other hand, if the long-term consequences are more important, then the second diference is greater. Te frst diference compares two non-extinction outcomes, whereas the second diference compares a non-extinction outcome with an extinction outcome—and only the extinction outcome means that the future would be forever lost. Tis thought-experiment was conceived by the well-known philosopher Derek Parft11 (we have adapted the three outcomes slightly; see the Methods section). Parft argued that most people would fnd the frst diference to be greater, but he himself thought that the second diference is greater. Many other philosophers and other academics working to reduce the risk of human extinction agree with Parft12–15. On their view, the badness of human extinction is greatly dependent on how long the future would otherwise be, and what the quality of future people’s lives would be. As the philosopher Nick Bostrom notes, predictions about the long-term future have ofen been lef to theology and fction, whilst being neglected by science16. However, in recent years, researchers have tried to assess what the long-term future may be like. Tey argue that if humanity does not go extinct, then the future could be both extraordinarily long and extraordinarily good, involving much greater quality of life than the current world. For instance, Nick Bostrom argues that a conservative estimate of humanity’s future potential is “at least 1016 human lives of normal duration”, which could “be considerably better than the average contem- porary human life, which is so ofen marred by disease, poverty [and] injustice”17. He goes on to argue that less conservative estimates would yield even greater numbers, and a drastically improved quality of life. Te argument is that if humanity develops to a sufciently high technological level, then it will either cause its own extinction via misuse of powerful technologies, or use those technological powers to greatly improve the level of well-being. Furthermore, they argue, based on the view that new happy people coming into existence is morally valuable11, that it is of paramount moral importance to make sure that we realize our future potential, and prevent human extinction. While philosophers have discussed the ethics of human extinction for some time, the general public’s views on this matter has not received much study. Tere are some studies on perceptions of risk of extinction, however. Two studies found that a slight majority do not think that humanity will go extinct, and that most of those who thought that it would go extinct thought that would happen at least 500 years into the future18,19. Tere is also a related literature on catastrophic risk in general, focusing primarily on non-extinction catastrophes. For instance, it has been argued that the fact that people use the availability heuristic—they focus on risks which have salient historical examples—leads to a neglect of new types of risks and risks of major catastrophes (which are rare, and therefore less psychologically available)20. Similarly, it has been argued that the fact that risk mitigation is a public good leads to under-investment, since it means that it is not possible to exclude free riders from benefting from it21. On specifc risks, there is a literature on the psychology of climate change showing that people fail to act to mitigate climate change because they engage in temporal discounting22,23 and motivated reasoning about its severity24, and because of psychological distance25 (e.g., temporal and social distance). However, to date there have been no studies on how laypeople reason about the moral aspect of human extinction: how bad it would be. Is the extinction of our own species something people care about? Do they recognize it as being fundamentally diferent in quality from other catastrophes? And if so, why? Results Study 1. In Study 1 (US sample, n = 183, mean age 38.2, 50.81% female), we studied the general public’s judgments of the badness of human extinction. A large majority of the participants (78.14%, 143/183 partic-

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    9 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us