Combinatorics in Banach space theory Lecture 2 Now, we will derive the promised corollaries from Rosenthal's lemma. First, following [Ros70], we will show how this lemma implies Nikod´ym's uniform boundedness principle for bounded vector measures. Before doing this we need to recall some definitions. Definition 2.4. Let F be a set algebra. By a partition of a given set E 2 F we mean Sk a finite collection fE1;:::;Ekg of pairwise disjoint members of F such that j=1Ej = E. We denote Π(E) the set of all partitions of E. Let also X be a Banach space and µ: F ! X be a finitely additive set function (called a vector measure). The variation of µ is a function jµj: F ! [0; 1] given by ( ) X jµj(E) = sup kµ(A)k: π 2 Π(E) : A2π The semivariation of µ is a function kµk: F ! [0; 1] given by ∗ ∗ kµk = sup jx µj(E): x 2 BX∗ : By a straightforward calculation, one may check that the variation jµj is always finitely additive, whereas the semivariation kµk is monotone and finitely subadditive. Of course, we always have kµk 6 jµj. Moreover, since we know how the functionals on the scalar space (R or C) look like, it is easily seen that for scalar-valued measures the notions of variation and semivariation coincide. By saying that a vector measure µ: F ! X is bounded we mean that kµk is finitely valued. This is in turn equivalent to saying that the range of µ is a bounded subset of X. More precisely, for every E 2 F we have sup kµ(F )k 6 kµk(E) 6 4 sup kµ(F )k: (2.1) E⊃F 2F E⊃F 2F The first inequality is obvious, as we have ∗ sup kµ(F )k = sup sup jx µ(F )j 6 sup kµk(F ) = kµk(E): ∗ E⊃F 2F E⊃F 2F x 2BX∗ E⊃F 2F The second one really says that there are not too many direction on the real line. In fact, ∗ fix any π = fE1;:::;Ekg from Π(E) and any x 2 BX∗ , and let + ∗ − ∗ π = fi 2 [k]: x µ(Ei) > 0g; π = fj 2 [k]: x µ(Ej) < 0g: Then, in the case where X is a real Banach space, we have k X ∗ X ∗ X ∗ jx µ(Ej)j = x µ(Ei) − x µ(Ej) j=1 i2π+ j2π− ! ! ∗ [ ∗ [ = x µ Ei − x µ Ej 6 2 sup kµ(F )k: E⊃F 2 i2π+ j2π− F 1 In the case where X is a complex Banach space, we get the same estimate with 4 instead of 2, by simply splitting x∗ into its real and imaginary parts. Theorem 2.5 (Nikod´ymboundedness principle, 1930). Let Σ be a σ-algebra of subsets of Ω and X be a Banach space. Suppose fµγ : γ 2 Γg is a family of X-valued, bounded vector measures defined on Σ such that sup kµγ(E)k < 1 for every E 2 Σ: γ2Γ Then, this family is uniformly bounded, that is, supγ2Γ kµγk(Ω) < 1. Proof. First, we may get rid of the Banach space X, just by replacing the original family of vector measures by the family of scalar measures given by ∗ ∗ x µγ : γ 2 Γ; x 2 BX∗ : Next, if we suppose that our assertion fails to hold, then there would be a sequence of measures from this family with total semivariations increasing to infinity. Conse- 1 quently, we may work only with a sequence (µn)n=1 of bounded scalar measures satis- fying supn kµn(E)k < 1, for E 2 F , and supposing on the contrary to our claim that supn kµnk(Ω) = 1. This was a kind of formality. What really makes the result difficult is that the measures µn are sign-changing, or even complex-valued. 1 1 By our supposition and inequality (2.1), there is a subsequence (µnj )j=1 of (µn)n=1 1 and a sequence (Ej)j=1 ⊂ Σ such that j−1 1 X jµnj (Ej)j > kµnj k(Ω) > n + 2 sup jµn(Ei)j for each j 2 N: 5 n2 i=1 N Sj−1 1 Put F1 = E1 and Fj = Ej n i=1 Ei for j > 2. Then (Fj)j=1 are pairwise disjoint and the above inequality implies that jµnj (Fj)j > kµnj k=10 for each j 2 N. Now, observe that the measures jµnj j=jµnj (Fj)j are non-negative, finitely additive and uniformly bounded by 10. Thus, in view of Rosenthal's Lemma 2.1, we may pass to an appropriate subsequence and assume that ! [ 1 jµ j F < jµ (F )j for each j 2 : nj i 3 nj j N i6=j Then, putting F = S F 2 Σ, we obtain j2N j 2 1 jµnj (F )j > jµnj (Fj)j > kµnj k −−−−! 1; 3 15 j!1 which contradicts the assumption about pointwise boundedness. Now, we proceed to the beautiful lemma proved by Phillips [Phi40], which has some truely deep consequences in the Banach space theory. Its original proof was technical and rather complicated. However, as it was shown in [Ros70], Phillips' lemma is an easy consequence of Rosenthal's lemma. One may compare the proof presented below with the one in Morrison's book, [Mor01, pp. 270{274]. The complex case will require the following well-known property of the complex plane, which we prove here for completeness. 2 Lemma 2.6. For any z1; : : : ; zn 2 C there exists a finite set J ⊂ [n] such that n X 1 X z jz j: j > 6 j j2J j=1 Pn Proof. Let w = j=1 jzjj. Divide the complex plane on four sectors bounded by the lines y = ±x. For at least one sector, say Q, the sum of the absolute values of all the numbers from the set fz1; : : : ; zng which belong to Q is at least w=4. With no loss of generality we may assume that Q is the sectorp given by jyj 6 x. Let J = fj 2 [n]: zj 2 Qg. Then, for every z 2 Q we have Rez > jzj= 2, thus X X 1 X w w z Rez p jz j p : j > j > j > > 6 j2J j2J 2 j2J 4 2 Remark 2.7. By using the so-called isoperimetric inequality, which asserts that the perimeter of any convex polygon does not exceed π times the diameter of this polygon, one may show that the assertion of Lemma 2.6 holds true with 1/π instead of 1=6, and this cannot go any better. 1 Lemma 2.8 (Phillips' lemma, 1940). Let (µn)n=1 be a sequence of bounded, finitely ad- ditive, scalar-valued measures defined on the σ-algebra PN. If for every E ⊂ N we have limn!1 µn(E) = 0, then 1 X lim jµn(fkg)j = 0: (2.2) n!1 k=1 Proof. First, by Nikod´ym'sTheorem 2.5, we infer that supn kµnk < 1. Suppose that our assertion fails to hold. Then, by a standard `sliding-hump' argument, we may construct 1 1 1 a sequence (Fj)j=1 of pairwise disjoint subsets of N and a subsequence (µnj )j=1 of (µn)n=1 such that jµnj (Fj)j > δ for each j 2 N, with some δ > 0. Indeed, the negation of (2.2) 1 1 P1 produces a subsequence (νn)n=1 of (µn)n=1 such that k=1 jνn(fkg)j > 7δ for every n 2 N, 1 with some δ > 0. Using Lemma 2.6 choose µn1 as one of the measures from (νn)n=1 such that jµn1 (F1)j > δ with some finite set F1 ⊂ N. Next, let m1 2 N be so large that max F 1 X1 X jνn(fkg)j < δ; hence jνn(fkg)j > 6δ; for every n > m1: k=1 k=max F1+1 Again, using Lemma 2.6, we may pick µn2 , where n2 > n1, as one of the measures from 1 (νn)n=m1 such that jµn2 (F2)j > δ with some finite set F2 ⊂ N n F1. Continuing this procedure we obtain the desired subsequences. By Rosenthal's Lemma 2.1, we may suppose that ! [ jµnj j Fi < δ=2 for each j 2 N: i6=j S1 Then, setting F = j=1Fj, we would get jµnj (F )j > δ=2; a contradiction. This is the time to hit the first target in Banach space theory, with the aid of Phillips' lemma. Let us recall that a Banach space X is said to have the Schur property whenever every weakly null sequence in X is norm convergent. 3 Theorem 2.9 (Schur, 1921). `1 has the Schur property. Before proving Schur's theorem, let us briefly remind how the dual space of `1 is represented in terms of measures. For any σ-algebra Σ the symbol ba(Σ) will stand for the Banach space of all bounded, finitely additive, scalar-valued measures on Σ, equipped with the total (semi)variation norm. ∗ Proposition 2.10. `1 is isometrically isomorphic to the space ba(PN), via an identifi- ∗ cation `1 3 ' 7! m' such that Z '(x) = x dm' for every x 2 `1: (2.3) N Remark 2.11 (before proof). The integration in formula (2.3) is with respect to a finitely additive measure. Such an integral is defined in a very the same way as the ordinary Lebesgue integral. Namely, let m:Σ ! X be a finitely additive vector measure, defined on a σ-algebra of subsets of Ω.
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages5 Page
-
File Size-