Bergson's Paradox and Cantor's Doug McLellan, July 2019 \Of a wholly new action ... which does not preexist its realization in any way, not even in the form of pure possibility, [philosophers] seem to have had no inkling. Yet that is just what free action is." Here we have what may be the last genuinely new insight to date in the eternal dispute over free will and determinism: Free will is the power, not to choose among existing possibilities, but to consciously create new realities that did not subsist beforehand even virtually or abstractly. Alas, the success of the book in which Henri Bergson introduced this insight (Creative Evolution, 1907) was not enough to win it a faithful constituency, and the insight was discarded in the 1930s as vague and unworkable.1 What prompts us to revive it now are advances in mathematics that allow the notion of \newly created possibilities" to be formalized precisely. In this form Bergson's insight promises to resolve paradoxes not only of free will and determinism, but of the foundations of mathematics and physics. For it shows that they arise from the same source: mistaken belief in a \totality of all possibilities" that is fixed once and for all, that cannot grow over time. Bergson's Paradox Although it's been recapitulated many times, many ways, let us begin by recapitulating the dilemma of free will and determinism, in a particular form that we will call \Bergson's paradox." (We so name it not because Bergson phrased it precisely the way that we will, but because he phrased it in a similar enough way, and supplied the insight that we expect will resolve it.) In this form it would be more accurate to call it a dilemma of free will and any rigorous scientific theory of the world, for although scientists today are happy to give up hard determinism for quantum randomness, the theories that result are no less vulnerable to this version of the paradox. Bergson's paradox begins with two observations about mathematics. First, mathematics is timeless: Euclidean triangles' interior angles have always summed to 180 degrees, and always will; nineteen has always been prime, and is in no danger of becoming composite. Second, mathematics is what delineates the way stuff moves around. Whether “stuff” ultimately cashes out to waves, particles, and/or something else, the way that it moves around in our world is one mathematically possible way among others. Each distinct way 1Actually the quote at the outset is from Bergson's introduction to La pens´eeet le mouvant, and the best defense of the insight is his paper [1] appearing in that volume; but the seeds of the insight are already present in L'Evolution cr´eatrice. 1 that all stuff might move around is called a \possible world" or a four-dimensional \block universe" (we will use the terms interchangeably) having a time dimension in addition to length, width, and height. Now our two initial observations make it legitimate, though not necessarily advisable, to imagine the ensemble of all mathematically possible worlds. Bergson, given the technology of his time, pictured them as film reels; today we might imagine a storeroom full of digital memory chips, each encoding one block universe. We will call this totality of all possible block universes the \Framework" of Bergson's paradox. The paradox then arises as the apparent contradiction between, on the one hand, this Framework's possible worlds sitting on shelves, and on the other hand, our immediate sense of free will, of our ability to influence the future, of responsibility and agency as we live our lives. Let us briefly spell out the contradiction. The Framework would identify our lives with swaths of bits in one memory chip. Somehow we (these swaths of bits) experience the sequence of states encoded in the chip as evolving over time. But seen from \outside," from the perspective of someone contemplating the storeroom of memory chips, our chip is just sitting inertly on a shelf like all the others. Bergson himself put it this way: [If we accept a block-universe-like framework] we will indeed get a universe whose successive states are theoretically calculable in advance, like juxtaposed images on a film reel before it unwinds. But in that case, what good is the unwinding? Why does reality deploy itself this way? Why couldn't it decline to be deployed? What good is time? ([1], p. 101) Time makes no sense in this Framework | it is ultimately just another static axis on which events are plotted, no different from the spatial axes. Personal freedom and agency are also nonsensical here. It would be crazy to suggest that bits encoded in one inert memory chip are even partly responsible for causing the distribution of the bits therein; it would be like saying that seven's being a prime factor of forty-two \causes" three to be another. Equally crazy would be the suggestion that some bits cause their block universe to become the real universe, as if a memory chip's contents could make it hop up and plug itself into some metaphysical computer, transforming it from a merely-theoretical universe into an actually-existing one. Needless to say, there is a whole ecosystem of objections and rejoinders to what we've just described; to those who have not already spent much time wading through it, the works of G. Strawson and D. Dennett are particularly worthy of recommendation. All we wish to insist on now is that what we've described is at least a prima facie paradox. The paradox's abstract form Let us abstract the form that Bergson's paradox shares with many other paradoxes. There is a Good Thing (in the present case, free will) that we understand intuitively to exist; and there is a Framework that seems to correctly capture the system in which the Good Thing resides; but the Good Thing can be shown, at least to the extent we can define our intuitive understanding of it, not to exist in the Framework; so we are left with three basic 2 options: (1) abjure the Good Thing, (2) claim that what we really must have meant by the Good Thing all along is some weaker, paler thing that does exist in the Framework, or (3) deny that the Framework correctly captures the system after all. Obviously many factors, varying from paradox to paradox, will influence which option we prefer | like how wedded we are to the Good Thing's existence, how sure we are that the Framework correctly captures the system, and how closely the weak pale thing approximates the Good Thing. The factor we wish to highlight here is the existence or nonexistence of a compelling alternative Framework. To see this factor's importance, let us cast the case of the Michelson-Morley experiment into this abstract form. The Framework here is the triumphant Newtonian/Maxwellian physics of the 19th century. The Good Thing is the invariance of the speed of light relative to all observers. Of course, this invariance is good in a rather different way than we consider free will to be good: we presumably have no personal stake in the speed of light, but it would be nice if our sciences incorporated its invariance, since the beautiful experiment of Michelson and Morley proves that it does obtain. In fact the experiment is so convincing, and the proof of its incompatibility with the Framework is so immediate, boiling down as it does to the observation that c + 1 = c cannot be true, that we would like to choose option (3) and scrap the Framework. Our point here is that, however ardently we might deny that a Framework captures its system, our minds will naturally drift back to it if there is no good alternative. In 1887 there was no alternative to the kinematics of Galileo and Newton; they underlay all of science and no one had concocted a way to escape them. It was only in 1905, after Lorentz and Poincar´ehad undertaken the difficult work of looking for a way and Einstein had fit all the pieces together into special relativity, that a fully acceptable alternative framework emerged. Alternatives to the block-universe Framework? Has anyone pieced together a compelling alternative, in the case of Bergson's paradox, to the block-universe Framework? Bergson certainly thought so: he intended his whole oeuvre to constitute an alternative. The hitch is that, as we said, the paradox at issue is the incompatibility of free will and any rigorous scientific theory of the world, and whatever merits Bergson's oeuvre might have, it does not ultimately amount to a rigorous scientific theory. We claim that no one else has developed such an alternative theory either, and that if we want an alternative, we must build one more or less from scratch. There follows a brief substantiation of this claim. The possible-worlds/block-universe Framework was first laid out explicitly, or at least first came to prominence, in certain works of Leibniz in the early 18th century. But for the remainder of that century, and for the whole of the 19th, it was rarely invoked directly. This was partly because Leibniz's claim that ours is the best possible world had been mocked and discredited right off the bat, and partly because scientific progress seemed to be proving our world fully deterministic, rendering the contemplation of alternate worlds somewhat beside the point. The situation changed in the early 20th century. The quantum revolution put an end to hard determinism, and the rise of logical positivism and logical atomism brought 3 Leibniz's philosophical approaches back to prominence in a more systematic form.
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages12 Page
-
File Size-