A New Characterization of Injective and Surjective Functions and Group Homomorphisms

A New Characterization of Injective and Surjective Functions and Group Homomorphisms

A new characterization of injective and surjective functions and group homomorphisms ANDREI TIBERIU PANTEA* Abstract. A model of a function f between two non-empty sets is defined to be a factorization f ¼ i, where ¼ is a surjective function and i is an injective Æ ± function. In this note we shall prove that a function f is injective (respectively surjective) if and only if it has a final (respectively initial) model. A similar result, for groups, is also proven. Keywords: factorization of morphisms, injective/surjective maps, initial/final objects MSC: Primary 03E20; Secondary 20A99 1 Introduction and preliminary remarks In this paper we consider the sets taken into account to be non-empty and groups denoted differently to be disjoint. For basic concepts on sets and functions see [1]. It is a well known fact that any function f : A B can be written as the composition of a surjective function ! followed by an injective function. Indeed, f f 0 id , where f 0 : A Im(f ) is the restriction Æ ± B ! of f to Im(f ) is one such factorization. Moreover, it is an elementary exercise to prove that this factorization is unique up to an isomorphism: i.e. if f i ¼, i : A X , ¼: X B is 1 ¡ Æ ±¢ ! 1 ! another factorization for f , then we easily see that X i ¡ Im(f ) and that ¼ i ¡ f 0. The Æ Æ ± purpose of this note is to study the dual problem. Let f : A B be a function. We shall define ! a model of the function f to be a triple (X ,i,¼) made up of a set X , an injective function i : A X and a surjective function ¼: X B such that f ¼ i, that is, the following diagram ! ! Æ ± is commutative. A model (X ,i,¼) for the function f is called an initial model if for any other model (Y , j,p) of the function f there is a unique function g : Y X such that g j i and p g ¼.A ! ± Æ ± Æ model (X ,i,¼) for the function f is called a final model if for any other model (Y , j,p) of the function f there is a unique function g : X Y such that g i j and ¼ g p. ! ± Æ ± Æ *FACULTY OF AUTOMATIC CONTROL AND COMPUTERS,UNIVERSITY POLITEHNICAOF BUCHAREST,SPLAIUL INDEPENDEN ¸TEI 313, RO-060042 BUCHAREST 6, ROMANIAAND FACULTY OF MATHEMATICS AND COMPUTER SCIENCE,UNIVERSITYOF BUCHAREST,STR.ACADEMIEI 14, RO-010014 BUCHAREST 1, ROMANIA [email protected] 1 f A B i ¼ X Remark 1.1. For any function f : A B, there is at least one model. ! We may consider that A and B do not have any elements in common, otherwise, just consider a set B 0 B. Indeed, it is easy to see the remark is true if we consider X A B, Æ» Æ [ consider i to be the canonical injection and define ( f (a), if a A ¼(x) 2 . Æ b, if b B 2 2 Initial and final models of a function The next theorem gives a new characterization of injective and surjective maps. Theorem 2.1. Let f : A B be a function. Then: ! a) f has a final model if and only if f is injective. b) f has an initial model if and only if f is surjective. Proof. a) " " Let f be an injective function. In this case, (B, f ,id ) is obviously a model (Æ B for f and we will now show that it is a final model. Let (Y , j,p) be another model. We want there to be a unique function g : Y B such that g j f and id g p. The existence is ! ± Æ B ± Æ obvious since g p satisfies the relations. The uniqueness is given by the fact that id g p, Æ B ± Æ and so the unique function that satisfies this is g p. Æ " " Let f : A B, assume (X ,i,¼) is a final model of f and ® X . Suppose f is not Æ) ! 62 injective. Therefore, there are two elements of A, a a such that f (a ) f (a ). Let Y 1 6Æ 2 1 Æ 2 Æ X {®}. We define j : A Y and p : Y B such that [ ! ! ( ¼(x), if y X j(a) i(a) and p(x) 2 , Æ Æ f (a ), if y ® 1 Æ a A and y Y . 8 2 8 2 With this construction, (Y , j,p) is a model for f as a A, 8 2 (p j)(a) p ¡j (a)¢ p (i (a)) ¼(i (a)) f (a), ± Æ Æ Æ Æ since i(a) X and (X ,i,¼) is a model for f . We now define g ,g : Y X as 2 1 2 ! ( ( y, if y X y, if y X g1(y) 2 and g2(y) 2 . Æ i(a ), if y ® Æ i(a ), if y ® 1 Æ 2 Æ 2 Then g g , since i(a ) i(a ) because i is injective. We are now going to prove that g 1 6Æ 2 1 6Æ 2 1 and g2 are morphisms of models (i. e. the triangles are commutative) which contradicts the hypothesis that X is a final model (X is final g g ). Firstly, Æ) 1 Æ 2 ¡ ¢ ¡ ¢ (g1 j)(a) g1 j (a) g1 i(a) i(a), ± Æ Æ |{z} Æ X 2 a A, which means that g j i and, analogously, g j i. Now, for y Y we have 8 2 1 ± Æ 2 ± Æ 2 ( ( ¡ ¢ ¼(y), if y X ¼(y), if y X (¼ g1)(y) ¼ g1(y) 2 2 p(y) ± Æ Æ ¼(i(a )), if y ® Æ f (a ), if y ® Æ 1 Æ 1 Æ and, analogously, ( ( ¡ ¢ ¼(y), if y X ¼(y), if y X (¼ g2)(y) ¼ g2(y) 2 2 p(y). ± Æ Æ ¼(i(a )), if y ® Æ f (a ), if y ® Æ 2 Æ 2 Æ In conclusion, g g and both g g and g g commutatively close the diagram 1 6Æ 2 Æ 1 Æ 2 f A B i ¼ X j p g X {®} [ which contradicts the fact that (X ,i,¼) is a final model. The proof is now complete. b) " " Let f be an surjective function. In this case, (A,id , f ) is obviously a model for (Æ A f and we will now show that it is an initial model. Let (Y , j,p) be another model. We want there to be a unique function g : A Y such that id g j and p g f . The existence is ! A ± Æ ± Æ obvious since g j satisfies the relations. The uniqueness is given by the fact that id g j, Æ A ± Æ and so the unique function that satisfies this is g j. Æ " " Let f : A B, assume (X ,i,¼) is an initial model of f and { , } two different Æ) ! ¡1 1 elements which are not part of A,B or X . Suppose f is not surjective. Therefore, there exists ® X i(A) (otherwise, i is surjective, and so bijective and f ¼ i which implies that f 2 à Æ ± is a composition of surjective functions so it is surjective, contradiction). Let Y X {®} Æ à [ { , }. We define j : A Y and p : Y B such that ¡1 1 ! ! ( ¼(y), if y X {®} j(a) i(a) X and p(y) 2 à , Æ 2 Æ ¼(®), if y { , } 2 ¡1 1 a A and y Y . 8 2 8 2 3 Obviously, j is an injective function and p is surjective because p(Y ) ¼(X {®}) {¼(®)} ¼(X ) B. Æ à [ Æ Æ Moreover, (p g)(a) p ¡j(a)¢ p¡ i(a) ¢ ¼(i(a)) f (a), ± Æ Æ |{z} Æ Æ X {®} 2 à so (Y , j,p) is a model for f . We now define g ,g : X Y to be the functions 1 2 ! ( ( x, if x X {®} x, if x X {®} g1(x) 2 à and g2(x) 2 à . Æ , if x ® Æ , if x ® ¡1 Æ 1 Æ It is straightforward that g g , since . We shall now prove that g and g are 1 6Æ 2 1 6Æ ¡1 1 2 morphisms of models which contradicts the fact that (X ,i,¼) is an initial model (X is initial g g ). First of all, Æ) 1 Æ 2 ¡ ¢ (g1 i)(a) g1 i(a) i(a) j(a), a A, ± Æ |{z} Æ Æ 8 2 X {®} 2 à so g i j and, in an analogous way, g i j. Now, for p g p g ¼ we have to split 1 ± Æ 2 ± Æ ± 1 Æ ± 2 Æ our analysis into two parts: • If x X {®}, we have 2 à g (x) g (x) x p ¡g (x)¢ p ¡g (x)¢ p(x) ¼(x), x X {®}. 1 Æ 2 Æ Æ) 1 Æ 2 Æ Æ 8 2 à • If x ®, we have g (®) and g (®) , so Æ 1 Æ ¡1 2 Æ 1 p ¡g (®)¢ p( ) ¼(®) p( ) p ¡g (®)¢ 1 Æ ¡1 Æ Æ 1 Æ 2 which shows that p g p g ¼. ± 1 Æ ± 2 Æ In conclusion, g g and both g g and g g commutatively close the diagram 1 6Æ 2 Æ 1 Æ 2 f A B i ¼ X j p g X {®} { , } à [ ¡1 1 which contradicts the fact that (X ,i,¼) is an initial model. The proof is now complete. 4 3 Generalization to groups The term model used for sets can be generalized to groups in a natural way, by considering the functions to be group homomorphisms and the sets to be groups.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    8 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us