Lecture Notes

Lecture Notes

FOUNDATIONS OF ECONOMICS LECTURE NOTES BY OMER TAMUZ California Institute of Technology 2021 Contents 1 Preferences 4 2 Prices and consumer choice 6 3 Production 7 4 Private ownership economies and Walrasian equilibria 8 5 Walrasian equilibria with transfers 10 6 Excess demand 13 7 Compactifying the economy 15 8 Kakutani’s Theorem and Debreu’s Theorem 16 9 Existence of equilibria 17 10 Approximate equilibria 18 11 Scitovsky contours 21 12 The core 22 13 The core via approximate equilibria 25 14 Partial equilibrium: consumers 28 15 Partial equilibrium: production 30 16 Partial equilibrium conditions 31 17 Uncertainty 33 18 Pari-mutuel gambling 34 19 Radner equilibria 39 20 Asset pricing 42 2 Disclaimer This a not a textbook. These are lecture notes. 3 1 Preferences Let X be a metric space. We say that X is connected if it is not the disjoint union of two closed sets. A closed-contour preference on X is a reflexive, transitive and complete binary relation ¹ such that for each x 2 X the upper contour set {x0 2 X : x ¹ x0} and lower contour set {x0 2 X : x0 ¹ x} are closed subsets of X. We say that ¹ is a closed preference if it is a closed subset of X £ X; that is if {(x, x0): x ¹ x0} is a closed subset of X £ X. We say that a subset Q ⊆ X is dense if for each x 2 X there is a sequence (qn)n in Q with limn qn Æ x. Equivalently, X is equal to the closure of Q. Recall that X is separable if it admits a countable dense. Theorem 1.1 (Debreu). For every closed-contour preference ¹ on a separable, connected met- ric space X there is a continuous function u: X ! R such that x ¹ x0 iff u(x) · u(x0). Corollary 1.2. Let X be a connected, separable metric space, and let ¹ be a preference on X. Then the following are equivalent: 1. ¹ is closed-contour. 2. ¹ is closed. Proof. Suppose ¹ is closed-contour. Then by Theorem 1.1 there is a continuous utility func- ! R ¹ · 0 2 · 0 tion u: X that represented . Suppose xn xn for n {1,2,...}. Then u(xn) u(xn). If the two sequences converge to x and x0 respectively, then u(x) · u(x0), and thus {(x, x0): x ¹ x0} is closed. Conversely, assume ¹ is closed. Then {x0 : x0 ¹ x} Æ {(w,w0): w ¹ w0} \ X £ {x} is the intersection of two closed sets, and is therefore closed. We will henceforth assume that all preferences are closed (equivalently, contour-closed). We say that a preference ¹ on a metric space X is locally non-satiated (LNS) if for every x 2 X and " È 0 there is a x0 such that d(x, x0) Ç " and x0  x. We say that ¹ is convex if {x0 : x0 º x} is convex for all x 2 X. We say that it is strictly convex if ¸w Å (1 ¡ ¸)w0  x whenever w º x and w0 º x. Claim 1.3. If ¹ is convex then {x0 : x0  x} is convex for all x 2 X. Suppose X is convex. We will say that ¹ is convex* if 0 0 x  x implies ¸x Å (1 ¡ ¸)x  x for all¸ 2 (0,1). (1.1) Claim 1.4. If X is convex and ¹ is convex* then ¹ is convex. Proof. Let ¹ be represented by u: X ! R. We claim that (1.1) implies that u is quasiconcave, i.e., 0 0 u(¸x Å (1 ¡ ¸)x ) ¸ min{u(x), u(x )}. (1.2) 4 Suppose not, so that the above inequality is violated for some x, x0 and ¸. Denote v(®) Æ u(®x Å (1 ¡ ®)x0), and assume without loss of generality that v(0) · v(1). By assumption we have that v(¸) Ç v(0). It follows from the continuity of v that there is some ¯ 2 (0,¸) such that v(¸) Ç v(¯) Ç v(0) · v(1). But since ¸ 2 (¯,1), it follows from (1.1) that v(¸) È v(¯), and we have reached a contradiction. To complete the proof we claim that the quasiconcavity of u implies (in fact, is equivalent to) the convexity of ¹. Indeed, suppose that x0 º x and x00 º x, and assume without loss of generality that x0 º x00. By the quasiconcavity condition (1.2) xˆ Æ ¸x0 Å (1 ¡ ¸)x00 satisfies xˆ º x00, and so xˆ º x (the proof of the other direction is identical). Claim 1.5. Suppose X is convex, ¹ is convex*, and for every x 2 X there exists x0 2 X with x0  x. Then ¹ is LNS. 2 0  n Æ n¡1 Å 1 0 n  Proof. For each x X, let x x. The sequence x n x n x satisfies x x and intersects every ball around x. 5 2 Prices and consumer choice We consider a setting with L commodities {1,...,L}.A consumption space X is a subset of RL. Let ¹ be a preference on X. A price vector p is an element of RL. Given p and wealth w 2 R, the choice set X ¤(p,w) is given by ¤ 0 0 X (p,w) Æ {x 2 X : p ¢ x · w implies x ¹ x}. (2.1) Equivalently, X ¤(p,w) Æ {x 2 X : x0  x implies p ¢ x0 È w}. Lemma 2.1. Suppose ¹ is LNS, and x¤ 2 X ¤(p,w). Then x º x¤ implies p ¢ x¤ ¸ w. Proof. Suppose towards a contradiction that x º x¤ and p¢ x Ç w. Then there is some " small enough so that p ¢ x0 Ç w for all x0 such that kx ¡ x0k". Since ¹ is LNS, there is some such x0 such that x0  x. Hence x0  x¤, and so it is impossible that x¤ 2 X ¤(p,w). Claim 2.2. Suppose X is convex. Fix a price vector p, w 2 R and x 2 X such that x0  x implies p ¢ x0 ¸ w, and such that there is some xˆ 2 X with p ¢ xˆ Ç w. Then x 2 X ¤(p,w). Proof. Let x0  x. We need to show that p¢x0 È w. By assumption p¢x0 ¸ w, and so it remains to show that p ¢ x0 6Æ w. Assume p ¢ x0 Æ w. Since Á is closed and X is convex, for all ¸ small enough it holds that x00 Æ (1¡®)xÅ®xˆ  x. But for ¸ small enough it also holds that p¢x00 Ç w, in contradiction to the claim hypothesis. 6 3 Production In a setting with L commodities, a production set Y is a subset of RL. Given a price vector p, the optimal production set is ¤ 0 0 Y (p) Æ {y 2 Y : p ¢ y · p ¢ y for all y 2 Y }. (3.1) The indirect utility is given by vY (p) Æ sup p ¢ y. (3.2) y2Y ¤ This is also known as the support function of Y . Note that vY (p) Æ p ¢ y for all y 2 Y (p). For ¸ ¸ 0, we denote ¸Y Æ {¸y : y 2 Y }. The Minkowski sum of two non-empty subsets L Y1,Y2 ⊆ R is given by Y1 Å Y2 Æ {y1 Å y2 : y1 2 Y1, y2 2 Y2}. It is easy to see that 1. v¸Y Æ ¸vY . Å Æ 2. vY1 vY2 vY1ÅY2 . The Minkowski sum of two closed sets is in general not closed. However, if Y1 is open, Å Sthen Y1 Y2 is open for every non-empty Y2, since it is equal to the union of open sets Å y22Y2 Y1 {y2}. We denote Minkowski subtraction by Y1 ¡ Y2 Æ {y1 ¡ y2 : y1 2 Y1, y2 2 Y2}. Claim 3.1. Denote Y Æ Y1 Å ¢¢¢ Å YL. The following are equivalent: P ¤ 1. j yj 2 Y (p). 2 ¤ Æ 2. yj Yj (p) for j 1,..., J. Fix some price vector p, and let y 2 Y ¤(p). How does y change when we change p? That is, if y0 2 Y ¤(p0), what can we say about the relation between y and y0, given p and p0? Claim 3.2. Let y 2 Y ¤(p) and y0 2 Y ¤(p0). Denote ¢y Æ y0 ¡ y and ¢p Æ p0 ¡ p. Then ±p ¢ ¢y ¸ 0. Proof. Since p ¢ y0 · p ¢ y we have that p ¢ ¢y · 0 Likewise, p0 ¢ y0 ¸ p0 ¢ y, and so 0 p ¢ ¢y ¸ 0. Subtracting the first from the second yields the desired result. 7 4 Private ownership economies and Walrasian equilib- ria A private ownership economy consists of the following elements: 1. L commodities. L 2. I consumers, each with a consumption set X i ½ R , a preference ¹i on X i, and an L endowment ei 2 R . 3. J firms, each with a production set Yj. P 4. Each consumer i holds a stake θi j in firm j. We assume i θi j Æ 1 for all j. P P P An allocation is a pair ((xi)i,(yj) j) such that xi 2 X i, yj 2 Yj and i xi Æ i ei Å j yj. The set of all allocations is denoted by A. A Walrasian equilibrium consists of a price vector p together with consumption vectors (xi)i and production vectors (yj) j such that P 2 ¤ Æ ¢ Å θ ¢ 1. For all i, xi X i (p,wi), where wi p ei j i j p yj.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    45 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us