
SYMPOSIUM: JOHN RAWLS'S A Theory of Justice A Theory of Justice.JoHN RAwLs. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Cambridge, Mass. 1971. Pp. xv, 607. $15.00. The Theory of Justice Dan W. Brockt Moral and value judgments are viewed by many people as at base subjective, nonrational, and incapable of proof. In academic moral philosophy this view is reflected in the dominance in much of this century of what is known as meta-ethics-roughly, the logical analysis of moral language and of the structure of moral reasoning. Meta-ethics is concerned largely with philosophical questions about ethics rather than with substantive moral theories or issues themselves. This focus on meta-ethics, as well as the linguistic or analytic movement in philosophy generally, has vastly increased the philosophical sophistica- tion and rigor of contemporary ethics. But on the debit side, moral and, in turn, political philosophers often have had very little to say directly relevant to the pressing moral issues of our time, and students as well as the general public have learned to look elsewhere for serious reflection on these issues. This is not to say that substantive moral and political philosophy has ceased to exist. Utilitarianism, the view that human actions and social institutions are morally justified to the extent that they tend to maximize the happiness of those they affect, has long engaged the in- terest and allegiance of many moral philosophers; it is a simple and systematic theory, capable of serving both as an individual ethic and as a social and political philosophy. But utilitarianism has the fatal draw- backs of conflicting at important points with most persons' considered moral judgments, particularly those on justice, and of failing to provide a firm basis for our western liberal political tradition with its emphasis t Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Brown University. The Theory of Justice on liberty and individual rights. A clear, systematic alternative moral theory has generally eluded moral philosophers. The social contract theory has been a leading alternative to utilitarianism as a social and political theory, but in traditional formulations such as Locke's it too has well-known difficulties and relatively few contemporary adherents. Two central tasks then face contemporary moral and political philosophers. First, there is need for a broader and richer view of moral philosophy, one that firmly establishes the rational and philo- sophical bases of substantive or normative ethics and restores it to a place at the least co-equal with meta-ethics. Second, a systematic alterna- tive to utilitarianism must be formulated to enable moral philosophers to proceed beyond piecemeal criticism and patching-up of utilitarianism and to illuminate the deeper issues dividing competing moral concep- tions. In masterfully fulfilling both these extremely formidable tasks, John Rawls's book A Theory of Justice is perhaps the most important work of moral and political philosophy of this century. Rawls has re- newed the social contract tradition in a highly sophisticated and attrac- tive form that makes use of recent work in decision theory and eco- nomics and is not subject to the usual objections to contract theory, while at the same time presenting with great power the systematic al- ternative moral theory to utilitarianism that has long been wanting. I One goal for a moral theory is, to the extent possible, to give order and coherence, a rational structure, to our moral beliefs and thereby to show them to be more than simply a jumbled assortment of prejudice, self-interest, etc. On this view, a moral theory is modeled on the lines of a scientific theory and tested by its capacity to give order to our con- sidered moral beliefs, to account for the different relative strength with which those beliefs are held, and to lend clarity and precision to our areas of moral uncertainty. By reducing all of morality to a single prin- ciple from which all secondary principles and particular judgments are derived, utilitarianism proposes one such structure. Rawls successfully shows over a wide range of cases that his theory of justice satisfies the test better than alternative theories such as utilitarianism. Never- theless, since people's considered moral judgments change and con- flict, it is not enough that a moral theory best fits and orders one particular set of such judgments. Rawls's reinterpretation of social contract theory in effect offers another test of a moral theory. Traditional social contract theory focuses on an agreement between persons in a "state of -nature"to enter into a society and to establish a government that they will be obligated The University of Chicago Law Review [40:486 to obey; it is primarily a theory of political obligation. In Rawls's ver- sion of the contract theory, the relevant agreement is on particular moral principles, here principles of justice. The force of the agreement in the original position (as Rawls entitles it) depends on showing that the original position embodies conditions widely accepted as reasonable for the choice and in turn justification of moral principles. An argument that a particular moral principle or theory would be accepted under such conditions in preference to all plausible alternatives is then an- other means of supporting the moral theory. Moral philosophy becomes on Rawls's view a special part of the theory of rational choice or deci- sion. The reformulation of social contract theory with the account of the original position is at the very heart of his entire philosophy and is, I believe, the most original and important element of his work. The fundamental idea of Rawls's theory is a simple and powerful one-the principles of justice are those principles that free and equal rational persons would agree on for regulating their common associa- tion. The conditions of choice in the original position give content and precision to this idea; they insure that the choice, and hence the princi- ples chosen, are fair to all. In this sense, fairness is the root moral notion in Rawls's theory. The function of the conception of justice chosen is, more specifically, to assign fundamental rights and duties, and benefits and burdens, within a society, to determine a proper balance between competing claims to the advantages of social life. A well-ordered society is one governed by a public conception of justice. Rawls organizes the features of the original position under four head- ings. "The circumstances of justice" are those conditions that make human cooperation possible and necessary: persons of roughly similar physical and mental powers living together in conditions of moderate scarcity, vulnerable to attack and having their plans blocked by others, and each primarily concerned to advance his own interests. "The formal constraints of the concept of right," and of justice in particular, are de- termined by "the task of principles of right in adjusting the claims that persons make on their institutions and one another." They are that principles be general (containing no proper names), universally applied, and "publicly recognized as a final court of appeal for ordering the conflicting claims of moral persons." "The veil of ignorance" under which persons choose principles is a crucial part of the original position. [N]o one knows his place in society, his class position or social status; nor does he know his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence and strength, and the like. Nor, again, does anyone know his conception of the good, the particulars of his rational plan of life, or even the special features of his 1973] The Theory of Justice psychology such as his aversion to risk or liability to optimism or pessimism ... [T]he parties do not know the particular circum- stances of their own society,... its economic or political situation, or the level of civilization and culture it has been able to achieve.1 Finally, "the rationality of the contracting parties" means that they prefer more of what Rawls calls primary goods-those things necessary to advance one's interests and plan of life, no matter what specific form they may take; 2 and that within limits they do not suffer from envy- they are not willing to suffer a loss themselves if only others have less as well. Some comment on the veil of ignorance is needed. I have said that the original position is designed to insure that the choice of principles and hence the principles themselves are fair. The principles of justice are moral principles, principles that would be chosen when persons take up the moral point of view, a central feature of which is im- partiality-moral principles should not favor our own position simply because it is our own. The purpose of the veil of ignorance is to deny to the contracting parties the knowledge of their own characteristics and circumstances that would enable them to propose or insist on principles designed to favor themselves. The veil of ignorance is not, therefore, simply convenient in bringing about unanimity on principles of justice in the original position; it is necessary to the condition there of taking up the moral point of view. It is irrelevant that persons are never in fact under the veil of ignorance and in general never come together in the original position to choose principles of justice. The agreement or con- tract is explicitly a hypothetical one, expressing what free and equal rational persons would choose for their conception of justice. There is no actual historical agreement; rather, one can take up the standpoint of someone in the original position, and so the moral point of view, at any time. The point of the veil of ignorance can be put somewhat differently.
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages14 Page
-
File Size-