Formal Semantics and the Grammar of Predication

Formal Semantics and the Grammar of Predication

Formal Semantics and the Grammar of Predication The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Chierchia, Gennaro. 1985. Formal semantics and the grammar of predication. Linguistic Inquiry 16(3): 417-443. Published Version http://www.jstor.org/stable/4178443 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:3716454 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Gennaro Chierchia Formal Semantics and the Grammarof Predication In this article I will discuss the semantics of predication in English and some of its implicationsfor syntax. Consider (1): (1) John is crazy. (1) says that John has (or instantiates)a certainproperty (or state), the propertyof being crazy. This, of course, is informativeonly to the extent that we know what properties are and what operations we can performon them (for example, under what conditions we can conjoin two properties or attributea property to an individual). Suppose it is possible to determinethe set of operationswe can performon propertiesand to use the resultingstructure in spellingout the semanticsof predicativeconstructions. Presumably, there will be just a finite set of such allowable operations. Since there must exist some systematic relation between syntax and semantics, it follows that this will make pre- dictions about the behavior of predicative expressions. For example, it may set up a limited range of patterns that we should expect to find. Thus, a (semantic) theory of propertiesmight be a significantstep towarddefining what a possible grammarfor natural languages can be. I will argue that this is indeed so, by developing a semantic theory of properties and predicationthat tries to be highly restrictive, '"perhapserring in that direction," to borrow Williams's words. The approachI will develop is cast in the traditionof logical semantics. I will sketch an axiomatic theory of properties and its model-theoreticin- terpretation.I will then show how this theory, embeddedin an independentlymotivated theory of syntax, explains significantaspects of the way nominaland verbal predicative structuresbehave in English. A few terminologicalpreliminaries are in order. By property(or propositionalfunc- tion) I will refer to whatever Verb Phrases (as they occur in sentences like (1)) are semantically associated with. The main characteristicof propertiescan be taken to be that they can be meaningfullyattributed to (or saturatedby) a subject(or, more neutrally, an argument).' In this regard properties differ crucially from other popular semantic Versions of this article were deliveredat the Universityof Massachusettsworkshop on nominalizations (May 1983)and at the Ohio State UniversityTarski MemorialConference (April 1984), and I would like to thank the participantsat those conferences for helpful comments. The topics discussed here are developed more extensively in Chierchia(1984; in preparation),and the acknowledgmentsthere (especially those to E. Bach, B. H. Partee,and M. Rooth)apply here as well. I also wouldlike to thankR. Larsonand an anonymous referee for useful and insightfulcomments, and WalterBreen for his editorialassistance. The same holds, moregenerally, for n-placerelations. Within the traditionof logic, propertiesare usually regardedas 1-placerelations and propositionsas 0-place relations. Linguistic Inquiry, Volume 16, Number 3, Summer 1985 0024-3892/85/030417-27 $02.50/0 ?1985 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology 417 418 GENNARO CHIERCHIA creatures. Take individuals-for instance, the semantic values of simple Noun Phrases like Pavarotti. The bearerof this name, besides being a well-knowntenor, is a saturated particular;he cannot take an argument.We cannot attributeindividuals to other indi- viduals like we can attributeproperties to individuals.Consider next the semantic value of overtly clausal constructions (such as (1)), namely propositions. Propositions result when a property is saturated by (applied to/predicatedof) an individual in an act of predication. They share with individuals the fact that they are saturated structures (which, of course, does not imply that propositions are individuals).Various semantic theories of propositionsexist. For instance, it has been proposedthat such entities should be construed as sets of possible worlds, or as sets of situations, or as events, etc. Some approaches take the notion of proposition as primitive and provide an axiomatic (or algebraic)characterization of their structure.In what follows, I will focus on the nature of properties, while remainingneutral about the natureof propositions. Readers should feel free to fill in their favorite views concerningthe semantic value of Ss. 1. The Problem It can be argued that as speakers of naturallanguages we do not use propertiesjust to predicate somethingof an individual(as in (1)). We also refer to them and attributeother properties to them. We may even attributeproperties to themselves. Consider, for ex- ample, the following sentences. (2) a. Wisdom is hard to find. b. The property of being wise is hard to find. fBeing wise . C. To be wise is crazy. d. Wearingblack ties is a passing fad. e. Being crazy is crazy. (2a) contains a morphologicalnominalization and (2b) a gerundheaded by the nounprop- erty. Such examples clearly suggest that the domain of individuals we refer to must contain a way of representingproperty-like creatures. However, the nature of nomin- alizations such as those in (2a-b) is still largely unknown, which relegates our consid- erations to the realm of intuitions. I believe that a more compelling point concerning the fact that properties can also be argumentsof other properties (and, possibly, ar- guments of themselves) can be made in connection with (2c-e). To a certain degree, such a point will be theory dependent, for theories differ significantlywith regard to analyzing infinitives and gerunds. Four major currenthypotheses can be distinguished and summarizedschematically as follows: FORMAL SEMANTICS AND THE GRAMMAR OF PREDICATION 419 (3) Hypothesis Syntax Semantics Framework I nonclausal nonpropositional Classical Montague (VPs) (properties) Grammar(MG) II clausal nonpropositional Williams'spredication (S's) (properties) theory III nonclausal propositional Lexical FunctionalGrammar (LFG) IV clausal propositional Government-BindingTheory (GB) If hypothesis III or IV is correct, it is not clear that propertiescan be argumentsof other properties; but if I or II is correct, they obviously can. Thus, I and II seem to call for a semantic frameworkthat allows for propertiesto saturateargument positions of other properties (including,possibly, their own argumentpositions, as in (2e)). Our task will be to develop such a framework. Though various proposals have been made toward developing approaches with the characteristicsjust sketched (especially within the tra- dition of philosophicallogic; see section 1.2), the systematic study of the consequences that different property theories have for naturallanguage semantics has barely begun. In what follows I will adopt hypothesis I. In section 2.1 1 will propose a theory of properties and predicationthat accomplishes what hypothesis I seems to call for. I will then show how to implement such an approach within a theory of grammarthat can perhaps best be described as base-generatedsyntax plus compositional semantics. Fi- nally, in sections 3 and 4 I will discuss some empiricalconsequences of this semantics and compare it with other approaches(especially the Government-Bindingframework). 1.1. The Control Issue Within the limits of this article there is no way to do justice to the criticisms that have been leveled against hypothesis I (see, for example, Koster and May (1982)). However, I would like to discuss briefly the problem of control. If infinitiveshave no "'subjects" either in the syntax or in the semantics, why are they usually understoodas if they had one? Hypothesis I offers no obvious answer to this question, and potentially this con- stitutes an obstacle to bearing with what follows. Withoutany pretense of exhaustive- ness, then, I would like to recall some of the strategies that have been developed to handle control phenomenawithin hypothesis I. One possibility is to build into the interpretiveprocedure a device that inserts the missing subjects in the semantics. For example, althoughinfinitives like to leave denote properties(i.e. unsaturated,subjectless structures),something like John wishes to leave 420 GENNARO CHIERCHIA would end up having somethinglike wish' (leave'(j))(j) as its meaning.Infinitives would get their subjects by a semantic rule. This view is defended in detail in (for example) Klein and Sag (1982). A second possibility is to regard control as a matter of semantic entailments. Ac- cording to this view, something like wish is semanticallya relation between properties and individuals. Thus, for example, John wishes to leave says that the wish-relation holds between John and leaving, and its meaning (its truth-conditionalimport) can be represented as wish'(leave')(j). However, when such a relation holds, it must also be the case that in all the situations where what John wishes is the case (i.e. in the worlds of John's desires) John, in fact, leaves. Our intuitionthat there is an understoodsubject

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    28 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us