The Place of Development in Mathematical Evolutionary Theory SEAN H

The Place of Development in Mathematical Evolutionary Theory SEAN H

COMMENTARY AND PERSPECTIVE The Place of Development in Mathematical Evolutionary Theory SEAN H. RICEÃ Department of Biological Sciences, Texas Tech University, Lubbock, Texas ABSTRACT Development plays a critical role in structuring the joint offspring–parent phenotype distribution. It thus must be part of any truly general evolutionary theory. Historically, the offspring–parent distribution has often been treated in such a way as to bury the contribution of development, by distilling from it a single term, either heritability or additive genetic variance, and then working only with this term. I discuss two reasons why this approach is no longer satisfactory. First, the regression of expected offspring phenotype on parent phenotype can easily be nonlinear, and this nonlinearity can have a pronounced impact on the response to selection. Second, even when the offspring–parent regression is linear, it is nearly always a function of the environment, and the precise way that heritability covaries with the environment can have a substantial effect on adaptive evolution. Understanding these complexities of the offspring–parent distribution will require understanding of the developmental processes underlying the traits of interest. I briefly discuss how we can incorporate such complexity into formal evolutionary theory, and why it is likely to be important even for traits that are not traditionally the focus of evo–devo research. Finally, I briefly discuss a topic that is widely seen as being squarely in the domain of evo–devo: novelty. I argue that the same conceptual and mathematical framework that allows us to incorporate developmental complexity into simple models of trait evolution also yields insight into the evolution of novel traits. J. Exp. Zool. (Mol. Dev. Evol.) 314B, 2011. & 2011 Wiley-Liss, Inc. J. Exp. Zool. (Mol. Dev. Evol.) How to cite this article: Rice SH. 2011. The place of development in mathematical evolutionary 314B, 2011. theory. J. Exp. Zool. (Mol. Dev. Evol.) 314B:[page range]. Most of the attention given to developmental evolutionary critical to evolutionary theory because they determine the biology has focused either on the evolution of developmental distribution of phenotypes among the offspring of an individual processes themselves or on phenomena, such as novelty and (or pair of individuals) with a particular phenotype. Because genetic assimilation, which seem to force us to acknowledge evolution is a population-level process, we are ultimately development. My initial goal in this article is to consider how concerned with the set of offspring distributions associated with developmental biology must ultimately be a part of the rest of each parental phenotype in the population. We thus arrive at the evolutionary theory. In other words, I aim to identify where joint distribution of offspring and parental phenotypes (Fig. 1). development necessarily enters into any truly general evolu- This distribution is a central element of any formal evolutionary tionary theory, even when we are not explicitly studying the theory. evolution of development per se. Having considered this broad Transmission was long considered the domain of genetics, not question, I will return to a more traditional concern of development. This, however, was an artifact of focusing on evolutionary developmental biology—novelty—and discuss how alleles, which seem to be transmitted directly—without any the same principles that link development to directional, incremental, change can shed light on the evolution of novel traits. Grant Sponsor: Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada; Grant number: 410-2008-0400; Grant Sponsor: NSF; Grant number: EF 0928772. ÃCorrespondence to: Sean H. Rice, Department of Biological Sciences, Offspring–Parent Distribution Texas Tech University, Lubbock, TX 79409. E-mail: [email protected] I shall argue that the principle place where development Received 4 January 2011; Revised 5 July 2011; Accepted 11 July 2011 necessarily enters into evolutionary theory is in transmission Published online in Wiley Online Library (wileyonlinelibrary.com). across generations. Specifically, developmental processes are DOI: 10.1002/jez.b.21435 & 2011 WILEY-LISS, INC. 2 RICE f Individual parent evolving system. We denote an individual’s phenotype by and Population o (mated pair) the average phenotype of an individual’s offspring by f (this is the average phenotype of the offspring that the individual actually produces; it is thus a random variable and is distinct from the expected offspring phenotype, which is the expected value of the distribution of possible offspring phenotypes). An Frequency individual’s relative fitness (the number of descendants that it leaves divided by the average number of descendants for all Phenotype of offspring individuals in the population) is denoted by O.Bothfo and O are random variables, meaning that they have distributions, rather Phenotype of offspring Phenotype of parents that specific numerical values (i.e. we cannot know ahead of time Figure 1. Offspring distribution for an individual or mated pair and exactly how many descendants an individual will leave or offspring–parent distribution for a population. exactly what they will look like; Rice, 2008). The fact that mean offspring phenotype and fitness for an individual have distributions, rather than fixed values, means intervention by development. Classical population genetics is that we will be concerned with means, variances, and covariances framed in terms of allele (or haplotype) frequencies, and genotype of these distributions. We will also, though, be concerned with is generally mapped directly to fitness. Of course, this mapping the means, variances, and covariances of various values across includes (at least) two distinct parts: mapping genotype to individuals in the population. We thus need to distinguish phenotype (largely the domain of development) and then operations over random variables from operations over indivi- mapping phenotype to fitness (the domain of ecology, biome- duals in a population. Consequently, we will denote operations chanics, etc.). Because of the complexity of this mapping, though, over individuals in a population with straight symbols (such as f population genetics often takes it simply as a given, without for the mean phenotype in a population, ½½2f for variance in f, reference to the mechanics underlying why a particular genotype and ½½f; O^ for covariance between phenotype and expected has a particular fitness. relative fitness), and operations over random variables with Quantitative genetics, by contrast, explicitly considers the joint angled symbols (such as w^ for the expected fitness of an distribution of offspring and parent phenotypes. However, in most individual), hh2wii for variance in an individual’s fitness cases, a single quantity is abstracted from the distribution. This distribution, and hhh2; Oii for covariance between an individual’s quantity is either a measure of heritability (the slope of the linear relative fitness and heritability of some trait). regression of offspring on parents) or the ‘‘additive genetic variance’’ Using this notation and defining d^ as the expected difference (the covariance between offspring and parents). Originally, quanti- between mean offspring phenotype and mean parent phenotype tative genetics was seen as an extension of multilocus population in the absence of selection, the most general description of genetics, made tractable by assuming many loci, each of small, change in mean phenotype in a closed population (i.e. one with additive, effect. As a result, quantities such as additive genetic 2 no migration) is then (Rice, 2008) variance (VA) and heritability (h ), were defined in terms of the contributions to phenotype of individual loci. Under this definition, c co b o b the covariance between offspring and parents was seen as an Df ¼½½f ; O1hhf ; Oii1d: ð1Þ estimator of VA, which was assumed to be the real value of interest. The first term on the right in Equation (1) captures the change General Phenotype-Based Theories. Recently, there has been a due to deterministic associations between expected relative trend toward treating quantitative genetics as a first order fitness and expected offspring phenotype. The second term approximation to a general, phenotype-based, evolutionary captures the stochastic contributions, resulting from correlations theory (Rice, 2004b; Heywood, 2005). Under this formulation, between relative fitness and heritability (the biological inter- what really matters is the offspring–parent distribution, and this pretation of this term will be discussed below). The final term, d^, leads to a subtle but important shift in definitions: although captures change, such as that due to mutation or recombination, additive genetic variance and heritability were classically seen as that occurs in the process of reproduction. latent properties of an individual that could be estimated by the The key thing to note for now is that parental phenotype, f, relationship between offspring and parents, under phenotype- does not appear anywhere on the righthand side of Equation (1). based theories, they are defined by the offspring–parent What appears instead is offspring phenotype, fo. In other words, distribution. Specifically, heritability is defined as the regression what ultimately matters in evolution is the relationship between of expected offspring phenotype on midparent phenotype. the fitness of parents and the phenotype of their offspring (Frank,

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    9 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us