1 Introduction

1 Introduction

1Introduction Qu’est-ceque la littérature? Jean-Paul Sartre posed this question in Les temps modernes in 1948.¹ Twohundred years earlier,Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten had provided what remains alargely neglected answer: “LITERATURE is perfect sensate discourse” (MED §9;Oratio sensitivaperfecta est POEMA). This definition lays the foundation for Baumgarten’sphilosophical approach to literature, which is what this book is about.With constant and open-minded attention to concrete literarytexts –“facing poetry,” so to say – Baumgarten presents this definition as the resultofaradical conceptualization of literature: Iintend to demonstrate that manyconsequences can be derivedfromasingle concept of literaturewhich has long agobeen impressed on the mind, and long sincedeclared hun- dreds of times to be acceptable, but not onceproved. Ut enim ex una, quae dudummentehaeserat,poematis notione probari plurima dicta iam centies, vix semel probata posse demonstrarem. (MED,[preface], 4)² In intellectual history,Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, who was born on July 17, 1714,inBerlin and died on May27, 1762,inFrankfurt an der Oder,isknown as the last prominent representative of Wolffian scholasticphilosophy. He worked in an agewhen every great philosopher soughttopublish auniversalsystem of philos- ophy, spanning all the disciplines. Baumgarten’spublications reflectthis objec- tive with his oftenenormous monographs on aesthetics,metaphysics,ethics, ju- risprudence, and epistemology.His aesthetics thus belongstoaholistic philosophical system, and it must be considered from such aperspective.But it is his aesthetics – which he initiated with his 1735 master’sthesis, entitled Meditationes philosophicae de nonnullis ad poema pertinentibus,and extended with the two volumes of his Aesthetica,publishedin1750and 1758 – for which he is best known. With these works,heestablished the modern discourse of aesthetics and gave the discipline its name. Intellectual history has thus par- ticularlysought to determine whereBaumgartenfits in the development of major facets of modern aesthetic philosophy, such as the autonomyofart,the univer- sality of aesthetic judgments, and the subjectivity of aesthetic experience. My studyaims to intervene in the traditionalunderstanding of his aesthetics by out- lining how it developed the first modern theory of literatureand discovered the Jean-Paul Sartre, “Qu’est-ceque la littérature?,” pts. I–VI, Les Temps Modernes 17 (février 1947): 769 – 805;18(mars 1947): 961–988;19(avril 1947): 1194–1218;20(mai 1947): 1410 – 1439;21(juin1947): 1607–1641; 22 (juliette 1947): 7–114. Iheretranslate “poema” not as “apoem,” but as “literature.” See 2.1Ambiguity;5.1 Prose. OpenAccess. ©2020Frauke Berndt, published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the CreativeCommons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 License. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110624519-002 2 1Introduction central relevance of literature to philosophy. In brief, Iwant to show that as the “science of everything that is sensate” (KOLL §1;Wissenschaft vonallem, was sinnlich ist), Baumgarten’saesthetics is actuallyascience of literature. Baumgartendid not set out to demonstrate the value of literature to philos- ophy. But in workingonhis philosophical writingsand lectures,heended up an- alyzing, synthesizing,and contextualizing literature. It thereby became clear to him that aesthetics demands asensate realization; or put differently, aesthetics is always an embodied philosophy. In anycase, his aesthetics does not deal with literatureasbelles lettresorasamoral institution but rather as an epistemic ob- ject.Through his philosophicalwork, he discovers literature’sown unique ca- pacity to address philosophicalproblems.Although Baumgarten was aphiloso- pher and not aliterary critic, he was able to tackle his philosophicalproject only because he approached it as aliterarytheoristavant la lettre.His aesthetics is thus formativefor away of thinkingabout literature that would coalescein the comingcenturies,beginning in particularwith Friedrich Schlegel, who mo- bilizedthe concept of theory against the poetological tradition and wasthe first to programmaticallycall his poetics atheory.But no laterliterarytheorist would ever again match Baumgarten’sholistic view. Despite the scope and significance of his work on aesthetics, his insights into “the logic without thorns” (KOLL §1;lalogique sans épines) – amoniker for aesthetics thathequotes from Dominique Bouhours³ – werequicklysuper- seded by Immanuel Kant.⁴ GeorgWilhelm Friedrich Hegel does not even men- tion Baumgarten, and the European Romanticswereutterlyuninterested in his scholastic philosophywith its hundreds of numbered paragraphs in indigestible Latin.⁵ Baumgarten’saesthetics was thus relegated to oblivion, and his theory of literatureremains undiscovered, waiting to take its rightful place in intellectual history.This oversight is basedonasimple misunderstanding of the role litera- ture plays in his philosophicalproject.Literature was always at the heart of Baumgarten’stheoretical interests, beginning with his 1735 master’sthesis. Both his Meditationes and the later Aesthetica largely draw on literaryexamples, See DominiqueBouhours, La manièredebien penser dans les ouvrages d’esprit (Paris:Veuve de S. Mabre-Cramoisy,1688;facsimile, Hildesheim: GeorgOlms,1974), 11. See Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers, “Introduction,” in Baumgarten and Kant on Meta- physics,ed. Fugateand Hymers (Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press, 2018), 1–4. See Hans Reiss, “Die Einbürgerungder Ästhetik in der deutschen Sprache des achtzehnten Jahrhunderts oder Baumgarten und seine Wirkung,” Jahrbuch der deutschen Schillergesellschaft 37 (1993): 109–138;Egbert Witte, Logik ohne Dornen: Die Rezeption von A. G. Baumgartens Ästhe- tik im Spannungsfeld von logischem Begriff und ästhetischer Anschauung (Hildesheim: Georg Olms,2000). 1Introduction 3 at first predominantlyfrom lyric poetry,but later mainlyfrom the great epics and fables of antiquity.The passages he selects fascinate him because of their figural, poetic qualities – and not because they belong to the genre of lyric poetry. In the scholarship on Baumgarten, these passages are considered mere ex- amplesfor something else, namely,for the “science of sensate cognition” (AE §1;scientia cognitionis sensitivae). But if that wereactuallythe case, then one would expectBaumgarten to cite examples from other technical or fine arts.⁶ He does not.Onlyinavery few instances does he refertoother arts at all, and these references never carry epistemological weight.Baumgarten is thus concerned not with art in general but with literatureinparticular.And the con- cept of literature itself emergeswhen he abstracts from his examples and draws attention to the structure of literarydiscourse,the actual focus of his theory.This means that by the mid-eighteenth century,literary theory had developed not onlyout of genre poetics, as scholars have oftenclaimed, but alsoout of philos- ophy, albeit unintentionally. To understand this unintended articulation of atheory of literature, one needs to remember what Baumgarten’sphilosophical project of aesthetics is about.Heultimatelywants to radicallyalter the order of knowledge,asheclaims in the second letter of the Philosophische Brieffe von Aletheophilus,inwhich he introduces his project in 1741: “Whyshouldn’tatalented philosopher be able to work on aphilosophical encyclopedia in which he presents the sciencesthat be- long to philosophyintotalintheirrelationship to one another?” (PHB, 6; Warum solltenicht ein geschickterPhilosophsich an eine philosophische Encyclopädie machen können, darinn er die zur Philosophie gehörende[n] Wißenschafftenins- gesamt in ihrer Verbindungvorstellte?). Such an overview of human knowledge would have to consider both the upperand lower cognitive faculties,which mo- tivates Baumgarten to organize his approach to an encyclopedia differentlyfrom JohannHeinrich Alsted’sstandard referenceworkofearlymodern knowledge, the Encyclopaedia septem tomis distincta (1630). Baumgarten’soutline for aphil- osophical encyclopedia onlyappearedposthumouslyin1769 – it wasentitled Sciagraphia encyclopaediae philosophicae and edited by JohannChristian Förster – but in this earlier “silhouette” (PHB, 6; Schatten-Riß), he presents logic See Jochen Schulte-Sasse, “Aesthetic OrientationinaDecentered World,” in ANew Historyof German Literature,ed. David E. Wellbery et al. (Cambridge:BelknapPress of HarvardUniversity Press, 2004), 351; Frauke Berndt, “Halle 1735:Die Entdeckungder Literatur,” in Medialität: His- torische Konstellationen,ed. Christian Kieningand Martina Stercken (Zurich: Chronos,2019), 371–377. 4 1Introduction as ascience of rational cognition or distinct insight, and reserves the laws of sensateand vivid cognition, even if it does not ascend to distinctiveness in the most precise sense, for a specific science. He calls the latter aesthetics. als eine Wißenschafft der Erkenntnis des Verstandes oder der deutlichen Einsicht […]und behält, die Gesetze der sinnlichen und lebhafften Erkenntnis,wenn sie auch nicht bis zur Deutlichkeit,ingenauesterBedeutung, aufsteigensollte,zueiner besondern Wissenschafft zurück. Diese letzterenennt er die Aesthetik. (PHB, 7) It is thus apparent that Baumgarten estabslishes the “artofaesthetic experience” (PHB, 8; Aesthetische ErfahrungsKunst) as atheoretical and not as an empirical science. Aesthetics is intimately related and equal to logic, “its older sister by birth” (AE§13;soror eius natu maior), which substantiates

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    7 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us