The Temporal Orientation of Memory: It’S Time for a Change Of

The Temporal Orientation of Memory: It’S Time for a Change Of

G Model JARMAC 96 1–13 ARTICLE IN PRESS Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition xxx (2013) xxx–xxx Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition journa l homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/jarmac 1 Target article 2 The temporal orientation of memory: It’s time for a change of 3 direction ∗ 4 Q1 Stanley B. Klein 5 Department of Psychological and Brain Sciences, University of California, Santa Barbara, United States 6 7 a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t 8 9 Article history: Common wisdom, philosophical analysis and psychological research share the view that memory is sub- 10 Received 1 July 2013 jectively positioned toward the past: specifically, memory enables one to become re-acquainted with 11 Received in revised form 26 August 2013 the objects and events of his or her past. In this paper I call this assumption into question. As I hope to 12 Accepted 30 August 2013 show, memory has been designed by natural selection not to relive the past, but rather to anticipate and Available online xxx plan for future contingencies – a decidedly future-oriented mode of subjective temporality. This is not 13 to say memory makes no reference to the past. But, I argue, past-oriented subjectivity is a by-product 14 Keywords: of a system designed by natural selection to help us face and respond to the “now and the next”. I dis- 15 Memory cuss the implications of the proposed temporal realignment for research agendas as well as the potential 16 Time evolution limitations of measures designed to explore memory by focusing on its retentive capabilities. 17 Subjective temporality © 2013 Society for Applied Research in Memory and Cognition. Published by Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. 18 “What we observe is not nature itself but nature exposed to our theoretical propositions, absent strong conceptual and historical 41 19 method of questioning” (Heisenberg, 1958/1999, p. 58) grounding, run the serious risk of appearing as little more than 42 stipulation. The reader impatient with such analysis can skip to 43 20 “Asking the right question is frequently more than halfway to Section 3. However, I think this would be a mistake. The approach I 44 21 the solution of the problem” (Heisenberg, 1958/1999, p. 35) have adopted is something I believe we need more in psychology; 45 22 Add to these quotes the truism “one has a better chance of find- too often we have a tendency to rely on terminology in place of 46 23 ing what he or she seeks if one knows what it is he or she is looking carefully specified, conceptually grounded analyses of constructs 47 24 for” and we have a concise statement of the basic considerations of interest. 48 25 of scientific inquiry – as well as potential pitfalls. An answer to the To head off potential confusion with my use of phrase “now 49 26 question “what is it?” determines the questions we can ask about and the next” (see above), I need to make clear that despite 50 27 it, which in turn determines the answers nature divulges when it the use of the word “now” in my phrase the “now and the 51 28 “pushes back”. The trouble is that once we determine what it is next” the “now” is decidedly future-oriented. Analysis of the for- 52 29 we are looking for, simply asking questions of nature is not suf- mal properties of “present of objective time” reveals it to be 53 30 ficient; the questions must be the “right” questions. And therein instantaneous (e.g., Faye, 1989; McLure, 2005), becoming the next 54 31 lays a problem: If the questions posed are not the “right” ones, the “present” essentially as soon as it makes an appearance (e.g., 55 32 answers received will lack the resolution necessary to fine-tune our Husserl, 1964; James, 1890). It thus is a mistake to speak of 56 33 understanding of the object of inquiry. the present in any way that implies measurable duration (e.g., 57 34 Prior to addressing my thesis – i.e., that contrary to the belief of Loizou, 1986; McLure, 2005): The present is a process consist- 58 35 many lay persons and professional researchers, memory typically is ing in an endless series “nows” instantaneously transitioning to 59 36 not about the past; rather, its subjective temporal orientation is, and the “next” (as well as retreating into the past; e.g., Husserl, 1964; 60 37 must, of adaptive necessity, be oriented toward the future (what Loizou, 1986). What is subjectively present necessarily is ori- 61 38 I call the “now and the next”) – I first discuss the psychological, ented toward, and phenomenologically indistinguishable from (i.e., 62 39 historical and philosophical scaffolding that forms the basis for my instantaneous moments lack experiental resolution), what will be 63 40 treatment of memory’s temporal orientation. I firmly believe that present – i.e., the future. Even the well-worn idea of a “specious 64 present” (e.g., James, 1890; Kelly, 1882) requires inclusion of 65 protention – i.e., orientation toward the “next” – as an essen- 66 tial aspect of the present. In short, the moment of the present 67 ∗ Correspondence to: Department of Psychological and Brain Sciences, 551 Ucen is, formally speaking, instantaneous, an abstract point in a tem- 68 Road, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA 93106, United States. poral continuum moving toward the “next” and away from the 69 Q2 Tel.: +1 805 450 4645. past. 70 E-mail address: [email protected] 2211-3681/$ – see front matter © 2013 Society for Applied Research in Memory and Cognition. Published by Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jarmac.2013.08.001 Please cite this article in press as: Klein, S.B. The temporal orientation of memory: It’s time for a change of direction. Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition (2013), http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jarmac.2013.08.001 G Model JARMAC 96 1–13 ARTICLE IN PRESS 2 S.B. Klein / Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition xxx (2013) xxx–xxx 71 1. Goals of paper before the present image can be held to stand for a past original. 128 That condition is the fact that the imagined be expressly referred 129 72 In this paper, “the it of inquiry” is memory. In Section 1 I address to the past, thought as in the past. .But even that would not be 130 73 the question “what is it that we call memory?” My goal is to craft a memory. Memory requires more than mere dating of a fact in the 131 74 definition sufficiently inclusive to accommodate most of the phe- past. It must be dated in my past. In other words, I must think that 132 75 nomena that figure in modern taxonomies – including phenomena I directly experienced its occurrence” (James, 1890, Vol. 1, p. 650; 133 76 that historically have been seen as related to, but not part of mem- emphasis in original). 134 77 ory proper. To put it slightly differently, my intention is to cast One reason memory so often is associated with past-oriented 135 78 a net broad enough to capture most (hopefully all) the various subjectivity is the failure to appreciate that although memory’s 136 79 mental states and their behavioral correlates recognized as mem- operations depend on past events, such dependence does not log- 137 80 ory by modern “systems” approaches (for reviews see Foster & ically warrant the inference that memory, as experienced, is about 138 81 Jelicic, 1999; Schacter & Tulving, 1994; Tulving, 1985; Willingham the past. A failure to separate the how of memory function from the 139 82 & Goedert, 2001). purpose of memory function has led to the common, but logically 140 83 In the following Section 1 deal with the problem of deciding the indefensible, presumption that memory, being of the past, must, of 141 84 “right” questions to pose to nature. Granting memory is a property necessity, be about the past. 142 1 85 of organic matter, the principles of natural selection are uniquely Thus, our truncated view of memory’s temporality derives 143 86 positioned to serve as criteria for determining whether questions largely from a failure to appreciate a subtle but crucial difference in 144 87 addressed to nature are the “right” sort. Adoption of evolutionary the use of two grammatically related prepositions – of and about. 145 88 criteria has an additional, salutary consequence of supplementing While of implies “from” or “due to”, about, in a functional sense, 146 89 questions that probe memory’s capabilities (which have been the implies “for” or “directed toward” (note: About can also be taken 147 90 focus of most modern research; for discussion, see Klein, 2007; to mean “concerning”. This is not its functional sense, but rather 148 91 Klein, Cosmides, Tooby, & Chance, 2002) with questions concerned its referential sense. As we will see in a later section of this paper, 149 92 with its evolved function. When interrogated in with respect to memory can refer to the past – e.g., episodic recollection – but this is 150 93 function, the answers nature provides can be quite unexpected. not its primary evolved function: It does not imply it is for the past). 151 94 The question I address is one of central importance – the rela- As a result of this conflation, the exception is taken for the rule.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    13 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us