In B. Bryson (Ed.)

In B. Bryson (Ed.)

Rebecca Newberger 5 Goldstein What’s in a Name? Rebecca Newberger Goldstein is a philosopher and novelist. She is a research asso- ciate in the psychology department at Harvard University. Her non-fiction works are Betraying Spinoza: The Renegade Jew Who Gave Us Modernity and Incompleteness: The Proof and Paradox of Kurt Gödel. Her fiction includes the novels Thirty-Six Arguments for the Existence of God: A Work of Fiction, Properties of Light: A Novel of Love, Betrayal and Quantum Physics, Mazel, The Late-Summer Passion of a Woman of Mind and The Mind-Body Problem, and the volume of stories Strange Attractors. mid the divisions in thought which marked A the scientific revolution, the founders of the Royal Society insisted on binding together two contenders for the basis of natural explanation. As Rebecca Goldstein explains, there were deep commitments to the primacy of experimental A colour engraving within the ranks of the Royal Society that the new compound emerged. results, and to recognising underlying mathemat- of Gresham Two cognitive stances that had seemed to have little to do with one anoth- ical patterns. But the really powerful trick, then as College, home of the Royal Society er, except in their opposition to the system of natural philosophy dominant now, lay in finding how to bring them together. from 1660 to for centuries, were rendered equally necessary in the explanation of physi- 1710. cal phenomena. After a lecture given by Christopher Wren, then the Gresham College It was a time of epistemological urgency. A grandly unifying cathedral Professor of Astronomy, twelve prominent gentlemen, deciding that they of thought was crumbling.1 The all-inclusive view of the cosmos, laid down would meet weekly to discuss science and perform experiments, recorded by Aristotle and buttressed by the medical theories of Galen, the astrono- their intention to form a ‘Colledge for the Promoting of Physico- my of Ptolemy, and the theology of Christianity, had offered a way of Mathematicall Experimentall Learning’. explaining … absolutely everything. From the falling of objects to the It might not have been the most elegant of designations, but it did, in rising of smoke; from generation and decay to the four basic personality its very wordiness, portend great things. It gave notice to the hope – types; from the relation between body and soul to the pathways of the plan- because it was still, in 1660, only a hope – that two distinct orientations, ets; the supposed nature and reason for every aspect of the world could be one mathematical, the other experimental, would be pounded together extracted from an interlocking system that employed a homogeneous form into one coherent scientific method. The hope paid off, and it was from of explanation throughout. 1 There were, of course, political and sociological dimensions to this process, since the grandly unifying system of thought was not only scientific (or proto-scientific) but also religious and political, making challenges to the system ipso facto religious and political challenges. I will focus on the scientific aspects of the process, but it is of course naïve to think that this consti- 4 Seeing Further tutes the whole story. The history of ideas is hardly hermetically sealed against all but questions of validity and falsification. The form of explanation had been purpose-driven, or teleological, and take advantage of them. ‘You cannot help it, Signor Sarsi,’ Galileo exults in its scaffolding was the metaphor of human action. We explain human The Assayer, written in the form of a letter to a friend, ‘that it was granted actions by citing the end state that the agent has in mind in undertaking it. to me alone to discover all the new phenomena in the sky and nothing to The old system took this familiar model of explanation and expanded it to anybody else.’ apply to the world at large. ‘To be ignorant of motion is to be ignorant of nature,’ Aristotle had written, but by motions he meant not just displace- ments of bodies but such processes as becoming a parent, gaining knowl- Explanation Re-Explained edge, growing older. All were subsumed under the same conception: a And what question is more foundational than the question of what counts striving to actualise an end-state that was implicit in the motion and as a good explanation? All the great men whom we now associate with the provided the explanation, the final cause, for the course that the motion formation of modern science – Copernicus (1473–1543), William Gilbert took. The explanatory logic of human actions – based on intentions – was (1544–1603), Francis Bacon (1561–1626), Galileo Galilei (1564–1642), one with the explanatory logic of the cosmos. Johannes Kepler (1571–1630), William Harvey (1578–1657), René The working hypothesis behind teleology was, of course, that all natu- Descartes (1596–1650) Robert Boyle (1627–1691), John Locke ral phenomena and processes do in fact have goals, allowing them to be (1632–1704) and Isaac Newton (1643–1727) – were intensely involved viewed as potentialities on the way to being actualised. But every form of with the question of what form explanation ought to take, if teleology was explanation makes use of some working hypotheses or other, ascribing to truly to be abandoned, and there was by no means a consensus among nature the features that allow such explanation to work. The mode of phys- them. Two different orientations emerged: one rationalist, stressing ical explanation that was to supplant teleology, making essential use of abstract reason, the other empiricist, stressing experience. mathematics, also staked its claim on the world’s being a certain way. In some sense, this cognitive split was nothing new. It had made itself We are today understandably prepared to believe that the only reasons felt in the ancient world, in the distinction between the Platonists and the anyone might have had to cling to the old crumbling teleological cathedral, Aristotelians. It is probably as old as thought itself, shadowing two distinct in light of the superior science battering it, were speciously theological; intellectual temperaments. But the new rationalist and empiricist orienta- and, in fact, such reasons probably did motivate most of those who clung tions were not like the old. The rationalist orientation looked to mathe- to the old system. Still, there was nothing a priori fallacious about the old matics to provide the new mode of explanation. The empiricists saw the system’s assumptions about reality, just as there was nothing a priori true new scientific method as emerging out of experimentation. In responding about the assumptions that would replace them. to the need for a new mode of explanation to take the place of teleology, The grand old system was crumbling, and it made for a capacious space they became epistemological rivals, offering competing models to take the into which genius could expand. When foundations fall, everything can place of the old system’s final causes. and must be rethought. The exhilaration on display in the writings of the The men who met in Gresham College, London,2 had given notice, in new scientists bears witness to how bracingly liberating such possibilities their self-baptism, that the mathematical and experimental approaches can be, at least for those with the intellectual imagination and bravado to were not only compatible but collaborative; even, as it were, one. There is 6 Seeing Further 7 Rebecca Newberger Goldstein an important epistemological claim implicit in their stated intention to promote ‘physico-mathematicall experimentall learning’, and the claim was by no means demonstrable in 1660. The thinkers whose work inspired them could be divided into those whose stance was slanted toward the new rationalist understanding of physical explanation – Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, Descartes – and those who espoused the experimental understand- ing of physical explanation – Francis Bacon, William Gilbert, and William Harvey. This list suggests a geographical divide, with the rationalists on the Copernicus Francis Bacon Galileo Galilei Continent, the empiricists in England, which makes the ecumenicalism of the sources of inspiration all the more noteworthy. The temperamental distinction between the mathematical rationalists and experimental empiricists could be, in fact, so marked that we can well wonder how these scientific founders made common cause with one anoth- er against the old system. How can such different scientific temperaments, proffering such different answers as to what a scientific explanation ought to look like, have conspired to hammer out the new methodology? William Gilbert, for example, a luminary of the experimental approach, is acknowledged as the founder of the science of magnetism, and his exper- iments had been ingenious. He had carved out of a lodestone – a piece of naturally magnetic mineral – a scale model of the earth he called his terrel- Johannes Kepler William Harvey René Descartes la, or little earth, and with it he had been able to explain a phenomenon that had been known for centuries. A freely suspended compass needle pointed North, but later observations had revealed that the direction devi- ated somewhat from true North, and Robert Norman had published his finding in 1581 that the force on a magnetic needle was not horizontal but slanted into the earth. Passing a small compass over his terrella, Gilbert demonstrated that a horizontal compass would point towards the magnet- ic pole, while a dip needle, balanced on a horizontal axis perpendicular to the magnetic one, indicated the proper ‘magnetic inclination’ between the magnetic force and the horizontal direction. The experiments convinced him that the earth itself was a giant magnet. Galileo, his contemporary, Robert Boyle John Locke Isaac Newton 9 Rebecca Newberger Goldstein commends his work, but criticises him for not being well-grounded in Orb in Orb’.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    12 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us