![[0.94]Matching a Trope Ontology to the Basic Formal Ontology](https://data.docslib.org/img/3a60ab92a6e30910dab9bd827208bcff-1.webp)
philosophies Article Matching a Trope Ontology to the Basic Formal Ontology Richard de Rozario The Hunt Lab for Intelligence Research, The University of Melbourne, Parkville, VIC 3010, Australia; [email protected] Received: 19 May 2019; Accepted: 15 July 2019; Published: 18 July 2019 Abstract: Applied ontology, at the foundational level, is as much philosophy as engineering and as such provides a different aspect of contemporary natural philosophy. A prominent foundational ontology in this field is the Basic Formal Ontology (BFO). It is important for lesser known ontologies, like the trope ontology of interest here, to match to BFO because BFO acts like the glue between many disparate ontologies. Moreover, such matchings provide philosophical insight into ontologies. As such, the core research question here is how we can match a trope ontology to BFO (which is based on universals) and what insights such a matching provides for foundational ontology. This article provides a logical matching, starting with BFO’s top entities (continuants and occurrences) and identifies key ontological issues that arise, such as whether universals and mereological sums are equivalent. This article concludes with general observations about the matching, including that matching to universals is generally straightforward, but not so much the matching between relations. In particular, the treatment of occurrences as causal chains is different in the trope ontology,compared to BFO’s use of time arguments. Keywords: ontology; BFO; tropes; applied philosophy 1. Introduction The field of applied ontology came to prominence in the 1990s [1,2], driven by knowledge engineering issues. In order to achieve coherent and shareable knowledge bases, engineers and scientists sought answers to questions in essence like “what is the meaning of a physical quantity?” [3] or “what exactly constitutes a gene?” [4]. The similarity to questions raised in philosophical ontology was readily apparent [5], opening up the possibility of joint engineering and philosophical ontology research. Arguably, applied ontology is not merely the application of philosophy to other disciplines like engineering. Rather, the discipline also informs philosophy itself—at the very least by raising new questions about the existence of things, but hopefully also by novel approaches and answers to those questions. As such, applied ontology is one pathway in the journey of reconstituting a natural philosophy, in the sense of Dodig-Crnkovic and Schroeder’s connected conceptual engineering [6]. The interaction with philosophical ontology is especially visible at the foundational ontology level. Foundational ontologies1 deal with fundamental aspects of our world, such as “material objects”, “events”, “being part of” and so forth. They underpin ontologies of particular domains such as biomedicine or information systems [2,7] (pp. 115–139). Currently, one of the most prominent foundational ontologies is the Basic Formal Ontology (BFO) [8]. BFO is a realist ontology, based on a relatively small set of universals and relations2. That is, BFO asserts that the (real) universe can be carved up into universals such as objects, processes, 1 Also called “upper ontologies”. 2 BFO includes relations (as per the specification), but these are as yet not included in the bfo.owl file. The discussion here refers to the specification. Philosophies 2019, 4, 40; doi:10.3390/philosophies4030040 www.mdpi.com/journal/philosophies Philosophies 2019, 4, 40 2 of 12 boundaries and qualities. By “universals”, BFO means “ ::: what all members of a natural class or natural kind such as a cell, or organism, or lipid, or heart have in common ::: not only in the realm of natural objects such as enzymes and chromosomes, but also in the realm of material artifacts such as flasks and syringes, and also in the realm of information artifacts such as currency notes and scientific publications” [9] (p. 13). BFO has been successful in supporting engineering and scientific research in areas such as genetics, information systems and defence [10]. In previous work on the ontology of competitive intelligence [11], I developed a core ontology based on particularized relations, or tropes, which are fundamentally different from the universals that BFO is based on (discussed in detail below). It is beyond the scope of this article to review the arguments for and against tropes (of which there are many flavors), suffice it to say that tropes are prominent in ontological theory that addresses the nature and quantity of properties (like being “a chair” or “being red”) [12]. At the applied level, tropes as particularized relations provide a way to connect causes to the structural relations that define entities, providing a seamless foundation for both entities and causality [11]. From either perspective, universals vs. tropes is a core ontological commitment. The previous work compared the trope ontology to several other ontologies, but not BFO. Given the prominence of BFO, it is important for lesser known ontologies such as the trope ontology to provide at least some comparison, but preferably a “matching” to BFO. This is important because foundational ontologies often act as the “glue” to connect disparate domain ontologies and, if a matching is possible, it would link the trope ontology to the wider world of ontologies based on BFO. Moreover, given the subject matter of foundational ontologies, discussion of such matchings informs philosophical ontology—albeit with a constructive, rather than critical emphasis. Matching is commonly defined as “the process of finding relationships or correspondences between entities of different ontologies” [13] (p. 39). I include in this looking for points of similarity, where terms in one ontology can be coherently defined in terms of another. As such, “matching” reflects a perspectivist stance towards ontology. That is, it recognizes that different ontologies may reflect different aspects or viewpoints of reality (including perhaps some level of denial of that reality). In summary, this article examines how the trope ontology was matched to BFO and what ontological insights we might obtain from such a matching. The next section will briefly outline the trope ontology and the remaining sections will match core terms of the trope ontology to BFO. In the conclusion, I will provide some general observations about the results of the matching and the relationship between the two ontologies. 2. The Trope Ontology Given the relative obscurity of the trope ontology, I will provide a brief overview here. For more detail, see my previous research [11]. The trope ontology is grounded in a view that relations between entities are real and exist primarily as individual relations, rather than universal relations. For example, when John stands next to Jane, it is not just John and Jane who exist, but also the relation of John’s standing next to Jane. If John is also standing next to Jake, then that “standing next to” has a distinct existence from the “standing next to” of John and Jane. Moreover, these individual “standing next to” relations cannot exist without the entities that they bind. This strong dependence of relations on their relata supports calling such entity/relation constructions “tropes”, although it represents only one view of tropes [12]. Philosophically, I have defended tropes by following Armstrong’s reasoning [14] towards particularized universals, but rejecting Armstrong’s argument that “states of affairs” are needed to bind relations to objects [11] (pp. 29–30). In this way, particularized relations (tropes) become an alternative theory that underpins relational realism. At the applied level, this results in individually identifiable relations, which provide a very convenient way to implement change and causal relations (discussed below). Methodologically, I try to adhere to parsimony and minimize the different kinds of relations that are admitted into the ontology, if for no other reason than the effort required to carefully examine Philosophies 2019, 4, 40 3 of 12 each relation for coherence in the ontology. On the other hand, one typically tries to choose relations that are as expressive as possible—i.e., relations with which one can say or represent as much as possible. So, the key principle of parsimonious expressiveness (or “say the most with the least”) guides much of the work in the trope ontology. As such, the trope ontology is based on two main kinds of relations: mereological parthood and a primitive causality relation that ranges over the parthood relations. The semantics and formal properties of these relations are as follows. The two primitive relations are represented with a simple predicate schema: p(N, part, X, Y), (1) p(M, cause, A, B), (2) Here, N and M represent unique identifiers for each relation, typically constructed as a list of numerals3. The second argument in the predicate is the kind of relation (e.g., part or cause) and the remaining arguments represent the entities that the relation binds. A small digression is needed on the meaning of “kind of relation” in the context of trope theory. At first glance, it seems that “kind” introduces universals again. For instance, each individual parthood relation seems to instantiate a universal parthood. Might this not undermine the supposed “fundamental difference” (asserted in the introduction) between the trope ontology and a universal-based ontology like BFO? The short answer is “no”, for the following reasons. Firstly, these are not the universals
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages12 Page
-
File Size-