
52 Terry Pinkard Eldridge, R. (1989). On Moral Personhood: Philosophy, Literature, Criticism, and Self-Understanding. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Eldridge, R. (1997). Leading a Human Life: Wittgenstein, Intentionality, and Romanticism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Willem deVries Fichte, lG. (1971). Werke. Edited by I.H. Fichte. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter and Co. Fichte, J.G. (1982). The Science of Knowledge. Edited and translated by P. Heath and l Lachs. FOLK PSYCHOLOGY, THEORIES, AND THE SELLARSIAN ROOTS Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fichte, J.G. (1994). An Attempt at a New Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre. In: J.G. Fichte ABSTRACT. Almost fifty years ago, Wilfrid Sellars first proposed that psychological (ed.), Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre and Other Writings. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. concepts are like theoretical concepts. Since then, several different research programs Frank, M. (1997). Unendliche Ann/iherung. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp. have been based on this conjecture. This es~y examines what his original claim really Frank, M. (1989). Eitifiihrung in diefriihromantische Asthetik. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp. amounted to and what it was supposed to accomplish, and then uses that understanding Friedman, M. (2000). A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer. and Heidegger. Chicago: Open of the original project to investigate the extent to which the later research projects Court. expand on it or depart from it. Hegel, G. (1971). Werke in =wan=ig B/inden. Edited by E. Moldenhauer and K. Markus Michel. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp Verlag, 1971. (Abbreviated as Werke and volume number). Hegel, G. (2004) Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1. Introduction: Folk Psychology as Theory Hegel, G. (1989). Science of Logic. Translated by A.V. Miller. New York: Prometheus Books. Horstmann, R. P. (1991). Die Gren=en der Vernunft. Frankfurt a.M.: Anton Hain Verlag. Husserl, E. (1985). Erfahrung und Urteil. Hamburg: Felix Meiner. We use mentalistic or psychological terms constantly in describing, Kant, I. (1956). Critique of Practical Reason. Translated by L. White Beck. Indianapolis: The explaining, understanding, and generally coping with the behavior of others Bobbs-Merrill Company. and ourselves. For several hundred years in the modem era (until, say, 50 years Kant, I. (1964). Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by N.K. Smith. London: Macmillan and Co. Kant, I. (1987). Critique of Judgment. Translated by W. !>Iuhar. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing ago), the bad old explanation of how we do that and what exactly is going on Company. when we do seemed, well, not unproblematic, but at least uncontroversial in its Kant, I. (1998). Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Cambridge: Cambridge University fundamental outlines: We enjoy direct and privileged access to our own mental Press. states. This enables us, first, to abstract a set of psychological concepts from Larmore, C. (1996). The Romantic Legacy. New York: Columbia University Press. actual and self-intimating instances of psychological states. Furthermore, since McDowell, J. (forthcoming-a). Autonomous Subjectivity and External Constraint. Manuscript. McDowell, J. (forthcoming-b). Transcendental Empiricism. Manuscript. the psychological concepts we have are abstracted directly from self• Nagel, T. (2001). The Last Word. Oxford: Oxford University Press. intimating instances, first-person application of those concepts is Pinkard, T. (2002). German Philosophy 1760-1860:' The Legacy of Idealism. Cambridge: unproblematic. It is incorrigible and provides each of us with certainty about Cambridge University Press. his or her own psychological states. This knowledge is primordial. On its basis Pippin, R. (forthcoming). On Giving Oneself the Law. Manuscript. we build up knowledge of everything external to our minds. From the Richards, RJ. (2002). The Romantic Conception of Life: Science and Philosophy in the Age of Goethe. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. materials we have direct access to we (somehow) construct and apply concepts Schelling, F. (1927). Philosophische Briefe iiher Dogmatismus und Kriti=ismus. In: M SchrOter of physical objects and events. More problematically, once we have the core (ed.), Schellings Werke, pp. 47-112. Munich: C. H. Beck und Oldenburg. set of concepts and some knowledge of our own psychological states, we can Seyhan, A. (1992). Representation and Its Discontents: The Critical Legacy of German begin to apply psychological concepts to describe, explain, understand, Romanticism. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. interpret, and generally cope with others as well. This requires the assumption Sellars, W. (1949). Language, Rules, and Behavior. In: S. Hook (ed.), John Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom, pp. 289-315. New York: The Dial Press. that the observable behavior of others is tied to their internal psychological Sellars, W. (1953). Inference and Meaning. Mind 62, 313-338. states in the same ways and in the same kinds of patterns that we find connect Sellars, W. (1963). Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man. In: Science Perception and our own psychological states and behavior. The argument for that assumption Reality, pp.I-40. Atascasdero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company. is a pretty weak induction by analogy, and this was a stumbling block for the Sellars, W. (1997). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind (with an introduction by Richard Rorty and a Study Guide by Robert Brandom). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. In: M.P. Wolf and M.N. Lance (eds.), The Self-Correcting Enterprise: Essays on Wilfrid Sellars (Po=nan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, vol. 92), pp. 53-84. AmsterdamINewYork: Rodopi, 2006. 54 Willem de Vries Folk Psychology, Theories, and the Sellarsian Roots 55 picture as a whole, but the rest of the picture seemed so solid, so obvious, that hoary past and extended run, they argue that commonsense psychology is not most preferred trying to find some way to solve the associated "problem of only susceptible to replacement, we should expect it to be replaced. It is not other minds" rather than rethinking the whole picture. only a theory, it is a bad theory. It took several thousand years for folk physics About fifty years ago some brave souls started rethinking the whole to be superceded, even after Aristotle codified it well enough to enable some picture.) Principal among the attempts to revise the whole picture explicitly more or less clear-cut tests. Folk psychology has endured through the first few was Wilfrid Sellars's trail-blazing effort in "Empiricism and the Philosophy of centuries of serious efforts at scientific psychology, but as neuroscience Mind." Sellars proposes that our psychological concepts and terms are like advances, it, too will eventually succumb. We will find ourselves in the theoretical concepts and terms. In Sellars's picture our most primordial seemingly paradoxical position of denying that the psychological concepts in knowledge is not our first-person acquaintance with our own mental states, but terms of which we (currently) understand our own behavior really designate a knowledge of "medium-sized dry goods," the public, physical objects and any robust features of the world. In our current lingo: we'll end up believing events that form the arena within which we conduct our lives. Sellars argues that there are no beliefs. that we should reverse the hitherto standard picture that our knowledge grows The second major project that takes off from Sellars's proposal is not "from the inside out": if we begin with a knowledge of the public objects and concerned with the large-scale picture of the conceptual evolution of events that shape our lives and at least a rudimentary set of metalinguistic, psychological concepts in human society, but the small-scale picture of the particularly semantic, concepts, we would have all the material necessary to individual's development and· application of psychological concepts. If developing the psychological concepts that Cartesians think are simply given psychological concepts are like theoretical concepts, then one should elements of our mental lives. investigate whether the kinds of processes by which psychological concepts Sellars's proposal, radical at the time, struck a chord and has since become are acquired and applied by the individual are like the kinds of processes by enough of a commonplace that many no longer know its provenance. Sellars's which theoretical concepts are acquired and applied. Indeed, in (probably original idea has served as inspiration for subsequent developments that have unbeknownst) tribute to Sellars's suggestion, the investigation of the human picked up the notion that psychological concepts are like theoretical concepts. ability to attribute psychological states to oneself and others and utilize such If psychological concepts are like theoretical concepts, then our use of those attributions to understand, explain, and sometimes predict human behavior is concepts, even in our everyday attributions of psychological states to ourselves often called inquiry into (or the theory of) Theory of Mind.3 A number of and others, is like using or applying a theory. Commonsense psychology is psychologists are vigorously pursuing this project, e.g. Janet Astington, Alison itself, then, really like a theory. Gopnik, Josef Perner, Henry Wellman, Alan Leslie, and Paul Harris. Since While Sellars's proposal has
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages16 Page
-
File Size-