Expected Utility

Expected Utility

Expected Utility Bruno Salcedo Cornell University · Decision Theory · Spring 2017 1 / 42 motivating examples powerball 2 / 42 powerball 3 / 42 powerball 4 / 42 st. petersburg paradox • Flip a fair coin until it lands tails • If we flipped the coin n times, you get $2n • How much would you be willing to pay to participate? 1 1 1 ∞ 1 E[2n ]= · 2+ · 4+ · 8+ . = · 2n = ∞ 2 4 8 2n n=1 X ∞ 1 ∞ 1 E[ log(2n)]= · log(2n) = log(2) · n = 2log(2) ≈ 0.60 2n 2n n=1 n=1 X X 5 / 42 von Neumann and Morgestern simple lotteries • A simple lottery is a tuple L =(p1, x1; p2, x2; ...pn, xn) – Monetary prizes x1,...,xn ∈ X ⊆ R – Probability distribution (p1,...,pn), pi is the probability of xi • Let L denote the set of simple lotteries • Example: L = (10, 0.2; 5, 0.1; 0, 0.3; −5, 0.4) b 10 0.2 0.1 b 5 bc 0.3 b 0 0.4 b −5 6 / 42 simplex • Simple lotteries given a fixed set of prizes x1,...,xn correspond to points in the n-dimensional simplex n n ∆ = (p1,...pn) ∈ R 0 ≤ pi ≤ 1 & p1 + . + pn =1 n o p3 b x1 0.1 (0, 0, 1) b L b L bc b x2 0.3 (0, 1, 0) b 0.6 (1, 0, 0) p2 b b x3 p1 7 / 42 simplex • Simple lotteries given a fixed set of prizes x1,...,xn correspond to points in the n-dimensional simplex n n ∆ = (p1,...pn) ∈ R 0 ≤ pi ≤ 1 & p1 + . + pn =1 n o b x1 0.1 (0, 0, 1) b L L bc b x2 0.3 (1, 0, 0) (0, 1, 0) 0.6 b x3 8 / 42 lottery mixtures • For 0 ≤ α ≤ 1 and lotteries L =(p1, x1; p2, x2; ...pn, xn) and M =(q1, x1; q2, x2; ...qn, xn) with the same set of prizes, define αL ⊕ (1 − α)M = r1, x1; r2, x2; ...rn, xn where rk = αpk + (1 − α)qk • Example: L = (0.5, 10; 0.5, 5), M = (0.8, 10; 0.2, 5), α =0.6 0.5 b 10 0.5 b 10 b 10 0.62 bc b 0.6 0.5 b 5 0.5 b 5 bc bc 0.8 b 10 0.8 b 10 bc 0.4 b 0.38 0.2 b 5 0.2 b 5 b 5 9 / 42 geometry of mixtures • With a fixed set of prizes x1,...,xn, mixtures between lotteries correspond to points in the line segment between them • The mixture weights determine the location within the segment (0, 0, 1) M b b 0.2L ⊕ 0.8M k M − L k .8 0 b L (1, 0, 0) (0, 1, 0) 10 / 42 lottery mixtures • Also possible to mix lotteries with different prizes • Example: L = (0.5, 10; 0.5, 5), M = (0.8, 20; 0.2, 5), α =0.6 0.5 b 10 0.5 b 10 b 10 0.3 bc b 0.6 0.5 b 5 0.5 b 5 bc bc b 20 0.32 0.8 b 20 0.8 b 20 bc 0.4 b 0.38 0.2 b 5 0.2 b 5 b 5 αL ⊕ (1 − α)M = (0.3, 10; 0.32, 20; 0.38, 5) 11 / 42 expected utility • Reported preferences ≻ on L • A utility function U : L → R for ≻ is an expected utility function if it can be written as n U(L)= pi u(xi ) Xk=1 for some function u : R → R • If you think of the prizes as a random variable x, then U(L)= EL [ u(x) ] • The function u is called a Bernoulli utility function 12 / 42 expected utility axioms • Axiom 1: (Preference order) ≻ is a asymmetric and negatively transitive • Axiom 2: (Continuity) For all simple lotteries L,M,N ∈ L, if L ≻ M ≻ N then there exist α, β ∈ (0, 1) such that αL ⊕ (1 − α)N ≻ M ≻ βN ⊕ (1 − β)N • Axiom 3: (Independence) For all lotteries L,M,N ∈ L and α ∈ (0, 1], if L ≻ M, then αL ⊕ (1 − α)N ≻ αM ⊕ (1 − α)N 13 / 42 continuity • The continuity axiom can be thought of as requiring that strict preference is preserved by sufficiently small perturbations in the probabilities – If L ≻ M, then so are lotteries which are close enough to L (hatched area) – This includes αL ⊕ (1 − α)N with α close enough to 1 (0, 0, 1) N b αL ⊕ (1 − α)N M b b b L (1, 0, 0) (0, 1, 0) 14 / 42 independence • If L is preferred to M, then a mixture of L with N is also preferred to a mixture of M with N using the same mixing weights • Independence gives the expected-utility structure • Similar to the independent-factors requirement from previous notes (expected utility is a form of additive separability) 15 / 42 example • How do you rank the following lotteries? 0.4 b 600 0.8 b 1500 L bc M bc 0.6 b 400 0.2 b −100 • How do you rank the following lotteries? b b 0.1 1500 0.5 1500 0.2 b 600 0.3 b 500 L′ bc M′ bc 0.3 b 500 0.1 b 400 0.4 b 400 0.1 b −100 • Independence says that if you prefer L to M, then you also prefer L′ to M′ • Note that L′ =0.5L ⊕ 0.5N and M′ =0.5M ⊕ 0.5N, for some lottery N (which lottery?) 16 / 42 allais’ paradox • How do you rank the following lotteries? b 0.1 5, 000, 000$ L bc b 1, 000, 000$ M bc b 1, 000, 000$ 1 1 1 0.89 0.01 b 0 • How do you rank the following lotteries? 0.11 b 1, 000, 000$ 0.1 b 5, 000, 000$ bc bc L2 M2 0.89 b 0 0.9 b 0 • Many people report L1 ≻ M1 and M2 ≻ L2 17 / 42 allais’ paradox • Note that we can write 1/11 b 0$ b 1 b b 1, 000, 000$ 0.11 0.11 b 10/11 5, 000, 000$ bc bc L1 M1 0.89 b 1 b 0.89 b 1 b 1, 000, 000$ 1, 000, 000$ 1/11 b 0$ b 1 b b 1, 000, 000$ 0.11 0.11 b 10/11 5, 000, 000$ bc bc L2 M2 0.89 b 1 b 0.89 b 1 b 0 0 • Independence would imply that L1 ≻ M1 if and only if L2 ≻ M2 (why?) 18 / 42 von neumann-morgenstern theorem Theorem: (a) A binary relation ≻ over L has an expected utility representation if and only if it satisfies axioms 1–3 (b) If U and V are expected utility representations of ≻, then there exist constants a,b ∈ R, a> 0, such that U( · )= a · V ( · )+ b 19 / 42 proof of necessity • Suppose U is an expected utility representation of ≻ • Axiom 1 follows from the same arguments as before • For 0 ≤ α ≤ 1 and lotteries L =(p1, x1; p2, x2; ...pn, xn) and M =(q1, x1; q2, x2; ...qn, xn) note that n V αL ⊕ (1 − α)M = αpi + (1 − α)qi · u(xi ) i=1 Xn = αpi u(xi )+(1 − α)qi u(xi ) i=1 Xn n = α pi u(xi )+(1 − α) (qi u(xi ) Xi=1 Xi=1 = αV (L)+(1 − α)V (M) • From here, it is straightforward to show that ≻ satisfies axioms 2 & 3 20 / 42 independence and linearity • Fix the set of prizes so that lotteries can be though of as vectors in ∆n • The following proposition that, under axioms 1–3, preferences are preserved under translations • This means that the indifference curves are parallel lines Proposition: Given lotteries L, M ∈ ∆n, and a vector N ∈ Rn, if L + N and M + N are also lotteries and ≻ satisfies axioms 1–3, then L ≻ M ⇔ (L + N) ≻ (M + N) 21 / 42 M + N b M b A b b L b L + N b B Proof sketch: • If (L + N) and (M + N) are lotteries, then so are A and B • A =0.5M ⊕ 0.5(L + N) and A =0.5L ⊕ 0.5(M + N) • Since A =0.5M ⊕ 0.5(L + N), independence says that if L ≻ M then B ≻ A • Since A =0.5L ⊕ 0.5(M + N), independence says that if B ≻ A then (L + N) ≻ (M + N) 22 / 42 risk aversion risk attitudes • For the rest of these slides, suppose u is strictly increasing (our decision maker always prefers more money) and twice continuously differentiable • Risk-neutral decision maker – E[ u(x)]= u(E[ x ]) for every random variable x • Risk-averse decision maker – E[ u(x) ] ≤ u(E[ x ]) for every r.v. x • Risk-loving decision maker – E[ u(x) ] ≥ u(E[ x ]) for every r.v. x 23 / 42 jensen’s inequality • A set is convex if it contains all the line-segments between its points • A function is concave if its hypograph is a convex set • Risk aversion is equivalent to u being concave u(x) b u(x2) u(E[ x ]) b E[ u(x)] b b u(x1) x x1 E[ x ] x2 24 / 42 certainty equivalent Definition: Given u, he certainty equivalent of a lottery x is the is the guaranteed amount of money that an individual with Bernoulli utility function u would view as equally desir- able as x, i.e., −1 CEu(x)= u (E[ u(x) ]) • Risk-neutral decision maker – CE(L)= E[ x ] for every r.v.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    47 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us