Demystifying Schmitt Eric A

Demystifying Schmitt Eric A

University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Public Law and Legal Theory Working Papers Working Papers 2011 Demystifying Schmitt Eric A. Posner Adrian Vermeule Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/ public_law_and_legal_theory Part of the Law Commons Chicago Unbound includes both works in progress and final versions of articles. Please be aware that a more recent version of this article may be available on Chicago Unbound, SSRN or elsewhere. Recommended Citation Eric Posner & Adrian Vermeule, "Demystifying Schmitt" (University of Chicago Public Law & Legal Theory Working Paper No. 333, 2011). This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Working Papers at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Public Law and Legal Theory Working Papers by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CHICAGO PUBLIC LAW AND LEGAL THEORY WORKING PAPER NO. 333 DEMYSTIFYING SCHMITT Eric A. Posner and Adrian Vermeule THE LAW SCHOOL THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO January 2011 This paper can be downloaded without charge at the Public Law and Legal Theory Working Paper Series: http://www.law.uchicago.edu/academics/publiclaw/index.html and The Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection. Demystifying Schmitt Eric A. Posner* & Adrian Vermeule** Carl Schmitt is too important to be left to the Schmitt specialists. To their credit, the Schmitt specialists were the first to recognize this. In recent years many of Schmitt’s most important works have been given authoritative new translations,1 while intellectual historians and political theorists specializing (at least in part) in Schmitt and his contemporaries have labored to set Schmitt’s work in intellectual and historical context, explaining its content and significance for academics in other disciplines.2 The goal of open-access to Schmitt’s thinking, however, requires more than translation and historical context. Even when those indispensable first steps have been accomplished, there remains a barrier to entry for those who would draw upon Schmitt’s work to illuminate subjects such as the design and operation of constitutions, emergency powers, and the administrative state. The barrier is that Schmitt’s work grows out of and exemplifies a continental tradition of legal and political theory that is heavily conceptual and laden with jurisprudential jargon. Especially for American lawyers whose interdisciplinary toolkit is drawn from the social sciences that flowered after World War II, Schmitt’s thought seems relentlessly abstract and mystifying. In this chapter, we attempt to demystify some of Schmitt’s core insights by interpreting them in light of simple causal intuitions and models drawn from the social sciences, including economics, law-and-economics, and political science. The aim is not exegetical or historical; of course we do not suggest that Schmitt thought in such terms, or that the social-scientific interpretations we offer are the best contextual understanding of Schmitt’s ideas from the internal point of view. Rather, the aim is utilitarian. It is to make some of Schmitt’s ideas usable for research in other disciplines, and to illustrate a general approach to Schmitt that can be applied to all of his writings. * Kirkland & Ellis Professor of Law, The University of Chicago. ** John H. Watson Professor of Law, Harvard Law School. Thanks to Janet Kim for helpful research assistance. 1 Carl Schmitt, Legality and Legitimacy, Jeffrey Seitzer trans. (Durham: Duke University Press, 2004); Carl Schmitt, Constitutional Theory, Jeffrey Seitzer trans. (Durham: Duke University Press, 2008). 2 See, e.g., Ellen Kennedy, Constitutional Failure: Carl Schmitt in Weimar (Durham: Duke University Press, 2004); John McCormick, Carl Schmitt’s Critique of Liberalism: Against Politics as Technology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997); William E. Scheuerman, Carl Schmitt: the End of Law (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 1999); William E. Scheuerman, Liberal Democracy and the Social Acceleration of Time (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2004). 1 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1723191 In Section 1, we focus on Schmitt’s distinction between legality and legitimacy, and the associated idea that legitimacy often amounts to a strictly negative power on the part of mass publics to resist elite proposals, either through negative votes in referenda or through extralegal resistance. Although liberal theorists worried by the specter of a plebiscitary executive have cast these ideas in ominous terms, as a form of proto-fascist democracy-by-acclamation or “soccer- stadium democracy,”3 we interpret the ideas in terms of recent work on the political foundations of constitutionalism. Schmitt’s distinction between legality and legitimacy, we suggest, rests on the unimpeachable insight that constitutional rules amount to nothing more than “parchment barriers” unless supported by the equilibrium political strategies of officials, citizens, political parties and other actors. In this setting, Schmitt’s emphasis on the latent threat of mass violence amounts to nothing more than an attempt to dig down to the ultimate microfoundations of constitutionalism. In Section 2, we focus on Schmitt’s distinction between the norm and the exception. This distinction is related to legality and legitimacy, because Schmitt claimed that legality and legitimacy are convergent in normal times and divergent in exceptional situations. Yet the distinction between norm and exception raises separate issues as well, because Schmitt famously claimed that the exception necessarily has the potential to intrude upon the “closed system”4 of constitutional legality in liberal regimes. We interpret this point in terms of the economic distinction between rules and standards, and in terms of the lawyerly idea of purposive interpretation. Schmitt’s idea of “commissarial dictatorship” as a form of dictatorship that may violate certain constitutional rules in order to protect and conserve the overall structure of the constitutional order is a form of standard-based purposivism writ large. Interpreting Schmitt in our terms might just amount to a different form of translation, not from German to English but from jurisprudential to social-scientific terms. Yet we think there is more to it than that. Casting Schmitt’s insights in the more concrete and pragmatic terms of the social sciences might make it possible also to cast them, or some of them, in the form of testable hypotheses, letting the fresh air of fact into the occasionally feverish world of Schmitt scholarship. The ultimate aim would be to test whether and to what extent Schmitt’s work generalizes beyond Weimar, to other times and constitutional or political systems. This is an aim that will to some degree de-contextualize his work, yet it is the logical conclusion of the Schmitt specialists’ work in broadening access to his ideas. 1. Legality and Legitimacy: Political Foundations of Constitutionalism Schmitt’s last major work before the collapse of Weimar was Legality and Legitimacy, published in 1932. The work is in some respects inevitably time-bound and place-bound; in part, Schmitt was participating in the politically fraught legal polemics of the day, particularly 3 Stephen Holmes, The Anatomy of Antiliberalism (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1993) at 49. 4 Schmitt, Legality and Legitimacy, supra note 1, at 4. 2 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1723191 involving President Hindenburg’s use of the emergency powers granted by Article 48 of the Weimar constitution. In this sense, Legality and Legitimacy is the hardest possible test case for our aim of interpreting Schmitt in generalizable social-scientific terms. Perhaps the work is so pervasively a creature of its background circumstances that it is hopeless to try to salvage any of its ideas from the wreck of Weimar, in many respects an outlier case for constitutional democracies. Yet we think that Legality and Legitimacy pioneers several major insights that political scientists and lawyers interested in constitutionalism have recently begun to appreciate and explore, in most cases seemingly without any awareness of Schmitt. Although the richness of Legality and Legitimacy means that one is somewhat spoiled for choice, we will focus on the connections among legality, legitimacy and the issue of the political foundations of constitutionalism. Schmitt begins Legality and Legitimacy with a new typology of regimes, intended to supersede Aristotle’s threefold classification of monarchy, aristocracy and democracy (each of which has both healthy and degenerate forms – the degenerate forms being respectively tyranny, oligarchy and mob rule). In Schmitt’s taxonomy, there are legislative states in which the central locus of lawmaking is a representative parliament, jurisdiction states in which the courts develop freestanding legal norms, and governmental-administrative states in which the executive or the bureaucracy issues situation-specific decrees. One of the book’s main theses is that the legislative state equates legitimacy with legality, which Schmitt argues is an impoverished account of legitimacy. The problems with this equation are twofold. First, the general norms or rules of law enacted by representative legislatures through statutes typically assume a normal, stable state of affairs in which it is possible to imagine a “closed

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    16 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us