Moral and ethical questions for robotics public policy Daniel Howlader1 1. George Mason University, School of Public Policy, 3351 Fairfax Dr., Arlington VA, 22201, USA. Email: [email protected]. Abstract The roles of robotics, computers, and artifi cial intelligences in daily life are continuously expanding. Yet there is little discussion of ethical or moral ramifi cations of long-term development of robots and 1) their interactions with humans and 2) the status and regard contingent within these interactions– and even less discussion of such issues in public policy. A focus on artifi cial intelligence with respect to differing levels of robotic moral agency is used to examine the existing robotic policies in example countries, most of which are based loosely upon Isaac Asimov’s Three Laws. This essay posits insuffi ciency of current robotic policies – and offers some suggestions as to why the Three Laws are not appropriate or suffi cient to inform or derive public policy. Key words: robotics, artifi cial intelligence, roboethics, public policy, moral agency Introduction Roles for robots Robots, robotics, computers, and artifi cial intelligence (AI) Robotics and robotic-type machinery are widely used in are becoming an evermore important and largely un- countless manufacturing industries all over the globe, and avoidable part of everyday life for large segments of the robotics in general have become a part of sea exploration, developed world’s population. At present, these daily as well as in hospitals (1). Siciliano and Khatib present the interactions are now largely mundane, have been accepted current use of robotics, which include robots “in factories and even welcomed by many, and do not raise practical, and schools,” (1) as well as “fi ghting fi res, making goods moral or ethical questions. The popularity of internet use and products, [and] saving time and lives.” (1) They argue for daily life tasks, and the use of household appliances as that in the future robots and robotics will be “pervasive a substitute for human effort are amongst the thousands and personal as today’s personal computers.” (1) The fu- of different daily interactions most people have with tech- tures of robotic interaction with the general populace and nology, none of which tend to provoke ethical questions. the issues that may arise are of primary ethical concern. Thus, these are not the emphasis of this essay. Rather, the Many of the images conjured in the public psyche about focus will be on the future of robotics, and the moral and/ types of more pervasive robots come from science-fi ction or ethical questions that may become apparent with their novels, television programs, or movies that have exem- continued development. Key questions will be presented plifi ed technological incarnations of the monster in Mary by examining a brief history of robots and providing dis- Shelley’s Frankenstein. Iterations that are more benevo- cussion of the types and purposes of robotics as relevant lent, however, have also crept into the social conscious- to national public policy. As well, an examination of ro- ness, such as Data from Star Trek: The Next Generation botic moral agency will be delineated in order to provide or C-3PO from the Star Wars trilogy, and each and all guidance for what such policy should entail. This paper is have become popular cultural icons. While the technol- an overview of the ethical and policy issues with regard ogy to develop robots or androids to the level of iconic to current and future robots – and it is up to the reader to science-fi ction characters is certainly not yet available, decide whether robots possess moral agency. there is no reason to think that science will not progress to that level within the next century. Interestingly, these rela- Synesis: A Journal of Science, Technology, Ethics, and Policy 2011 G:1 © 2010-2011 Potomac Institute Press, All rights reserved Synesis: A Journal of Science, Technology, Ethics, and Policy 2011 tively modern fi ctitious examples of robotics in popular centered,” (3) and do not refl ect any explicit concern for culture are not the fi rst within written discourse. Artifi cial the robot. Asimov’s Third Law, “A robot must protect its creations of humans have been prevalent since antiquity, own existence as long as such protection does not confl ict as can be seen in the ancient Greek myth of Prometheus, with the First or Second Law,” (3) offers the robot some who created humankind from clay (1). Eighteenth century measure of autonomy and dignity – but again only to a creations such as Swiss-born Pierre Jaquet-Droz’s autom- point that does not confl ict with humans. These laws are ata of an artist, musician and writer (1) or the seventeenth meant to “constrain the people who build robots of expo- century Japanese karakuri ningyō mechanical tea server nentially increasing intelligence so that the machines re- and archer dolls (1) are precursors of modern automatons main destined to lives of friendly servitude,” (4) and and and robots. under Asimov’s schema, the rights or privileges of robots will forever be constrained to serve human beings without With progress comes questions moral or ethical questioning or legal changes (4). The differentiation between robots that could fulfi ll a do- The concept of robotic privilege is not constrained to mestic role (2) within a future society and modern auto- fi ction - Japan and South Korea have begun to develop mated machines are, in many respects largely cosmetic, policies or laws to guide and govern human-robot inter- and the practical and ethical issues generated seem to actions, and these policies differ. The Japanese govern- vary. Some may choose to focus upon the notion of prop- ment’s Draft Guidelines to Secure the Safe Performance erty rights and would-be effi ciencies, as Whitby notes of Next Generation Robots contained a number of legal through the following car illustration. If a person were and bureaucratic provisions for “logging and communi- to drive her car fast, with little concern for maintenance cating any injuries [robots] cause to the people” in a cen- or repair, the lifespan of that vehicle would be noticeably tral database (5). These provisions have been motivated shorter, ceteris paribus, than if the owner were to main- largely by Asimov’s robotic laws (i.e., harm that could tain the vehicle regularly and drive more gently (2). Most come to humans from robots), rather than concern for eth- people would not raise ethical issue with the owner of the ical treatment of robots and involve the use of additional car choosing to do this with their property – and Whitby sensors, and requirements for softer construction materi- notes: “...’you ought not to rev the engine so hard or spin als to limit human injury (6). Christensen notes that Japan the wheels’ contains a ‘prudential ought’, not a ‘moral will require supplemental shut-off mechanisms for robots, ought’. It means nothing more than that the car will last which are envisioned to accommodate the needs of an ag- longer if one refrains from such activities.” (2) But what ing populace that will require, it is argued, more automa- if we are talking about a robot or automation-device that tion to complement the shrinking labor pool (6). South possesses certain cognitive – or moral – capabilities? Korea, conversely, has developed a code of ethics for human-robot interaction, which attempts to defi ne ethical There are very few laws or public policies regarding artifi - standards that would be programmed into robots (7). Addi- cially intelligent and cognitively capable robotsi, and this tionally, the code attempts to limit some potential abuses is relatively understandable given that the technology to of robots by humans, although perhaps not to the extent produce such viable artifi cially intelligent robots does not that may be required given future technological advances. yet exist. That does not mean, however, that these types of For instance, there is no mention of protecting the being decisions can be avoided indefi nitely given the pace and or dignity of the robot, rather than preventing machines extent of AI and robotic (bio)engineering. Despite being from being used by humans to abuse other humans (7). fi ctional, Isaac Asimov’s “Three Laws of Robotics” seem This reinforces the human-focused nature of ethics and AI to occupy an important position in ethical, legal, and pol- policy as it exists currently. icy discussions about the activity, regard and treatment of robots. The First Law states: “A robot may not injure a The fi eld of “roboethics” is a relatively new academic human being or, through inaction, allow a human being to concept, and was fi rst described at a 2004 conference of come to harm,” (3) the Second Law claims: “A robot must philosophers, sociologists, and scientists in Italy (8). The obey orders given to it by human beings, except when goal of those involved was to discuss and debate the is- such orders confl ict with the First Law.” (3) These two sues involved in “designing, developing and employing laws focus on the interaction between humans and robots robots” (8). Paolo Dario argues a further need for these – and therefore are, as Weng, Chen and Sun argue “human- discussions, given the changing nature of robotic engi- G:2 Synesis: A Journal of Science, Technology, Ethics, and Policy 2011 neering – from a discipline where robots perform tasks are still not considered by law or society as fully moral assigned by humans to one where robots perform tasks agents, and are not permitted to enter contracts, and large- while interacting with humans in real time (8).
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages6 Page
-
File Size-