Text + Work the Menard Case

Text + Work the Menard Case

Text + Work The Menard Case edited by TOMÁŠ KOBLÍŽEK, PETR KOŤÁTKO & MARTIN POKORNÝ Prague 2013 Litteraria Pragensia www.litterariapragensia.com Copyright © Tomáš Koblížek, Petr Koťátko & Martin Pokorný, 2013 Copyright © of individual works remains with the authors Published 2013 by Univerzita Karlova v Praze Filozofická Fakulta Litteraria Pragensia Náměstí Jana Palacha 2 116 38 Praha 1, Czech Republic All rights reserved. This book is copyright under international copy- right conventions. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permis- sion from the copyright holders. Requests to publish work from this book should be directed to the publishers. This book has been supported by project no. M300090902: Lan- guage, Reality, Fiction: Philosophy and Literary Theory Regarding the Sources and Determinants of Sense. Cataloguing in Publication Data Text and Work: The Menard Case, edited by Tomáš Koblížek, Petr Koťátko & Martin Pokorný.—1st ed. p. cm. ISBN xxx 1. Fictocriticism. 2.Literary Studies. 3. Cultural Theory. I. Koblížek, Tomáš. II. Title Printed in the Czech Republic by PB Tisk Cover, typeset & design © lazarus CONTENTS PREFACE XXX Tomáš Hříbek THE MENARD CASE & THE IDENTITY OF A LITERARY WORK OF ART XXX Göran Rossholm APROPOS MENARD: A DISCUSSION OF THE CONCEPT OF LITERARY WORK XXX Petr Koťátko TEXT, WORK, INTERPRETATION: SOME IMPLICATIONS OF THE MENARD CASE XXX James Hamilton BORGES’ MENARD: HIS WORK & HIS INTENTIONS XXX Alberto Voltolini A SYNCRETISTIC ONTOLOGY OF FICTIONAL BEINGS XXX Karel Thein MENARD, THE QUIXOTE, THE INDISCERNIBLES XXX Jacques Morizot MENARD, FROM LITERATURE TO VISUAL ARTS XXX Karel Císař ARTHUR C. DANTO, AUTHOR OF THE TRANSFIGURATION OF THE COMMONPLACE XXX Roberto Casati PLAY IT: THE REPLAY THEORY OF MUSIC EXPERIENCE XXX PREFACE The influence and reputation of Pierre Menard, Author of the Quixote, is easily comparable to the impact of groundbreaking theoretical texts. Numerous philosophers, aestheticians and theorists of literature, music, or visual arts have been induced by this short story by J.L. Borges to reconsider the status of the literary work of art and the status of artwork as such, to rethink the relationship between work and text (and analo- gously: work and the score, work and its physical bearer), and to make explicit the significance of the cultural context and the authorial intentions for the identity of a work or the nature of fictional entities. These philosophical reflections were produced by the eccentric literary aspirations of Borges’ hero, as the goal of Menard’s plan is to create an original literary work whose text will be, word for word, identical with the text of Cervantes’ Don Quixote. To construe a fully independent literary work around a purely intellectual scaffolding is no trivial task. The narrative approach that Borges chose is an appealing one. The entire case is made accessible by a narrator with his own vested interests, driven by vanity so strong that it is clear his descrip- tion will never quite convey the originality, the seriousness and the significance of Menard’s project. Yet all this only makes the significance of Menard’s plan clearer to the reader – whereas the author is safely protected from any suspicion of naively enthusing over his own discovery or of being en- chanted by his own idea. Such artifice is inaccessible to the authors of the essays included here. Fortunately, the genre of an academic paper provides them with no room for taking an ironical distance from their own arguments. In this way they have become potential targets for the sarcastic remark, once addressed to Arthur Danto, that by drawing serious conse- quences from Borges’ little joke they demonstrate their lack of humor. However, this should not discourage anyone. No mat- ter whether we are intentionalists or anti-intentionalists regard- ing literary interpretation, we can surely agree that a literary work may have unintended non-literary implications and that the value of any theoretical arguments that it provokes is inde- pendent both from the intentions of the empirical author and from the (impersonal) intention of the work, whatever way this latter intention is construed. This is why in Menardian discus- sions we can often see Menard’s case reduced, complemented, told anew from scratch, transferred into various other art gen- res, generalized and otherwise emancipated from the original literary context. This occurs – in a sequentially increasing de- gree – in the present volume. The essays move from analyses of the identity of a literary work of art (and the problem of the relationship between text and work), as it is explicitly estab- lished by Borges’ narrator, to arguments that simply employ the Menard case as an opportunity for discussing broader is- sues of literary studies and philosophy of literature. Select es- says even abandon the field of literature altogether and move on to analogous issues in the theory of visual arts and music. Tomáš Koblížek Petr Koťátko Martin Pokorný TOMÁŠ HŘÍBEK The Menard Case & the Identity of a Literary Work of Art Abstract: The essay provides a close analysis of Nelson Goodman’s arguments in support of identifying a literary work with its text—the position known as textu- alism. This position results in a rejection of a widely shared notion that Pierre Menard created a new literary work of art. Opposed to textualism is interpreta- tionism, a theory put forward by Arthur Danto. According to interpretationism, a literary work is an interpretation of its text, in consequence of which multiple interpretations of the same text count as different works, Menard’s Quixote among countless others. However, Goodman and Danto no longer appear to be opposed to each other once we take into account Goodman’s somewhat later suggestion that a physicalistically (i.e., syntactically) same item could perform a variety of functions. Both Danto and Goodman can then be seen as defending variants of aesthetic functionalism—the view that a (literary) literary work can be identified in purely functional terms. However, aesthetic functionalism falls a victim to similar objections as its better known cousin in the philosophy of mind, and the most serious of these objections come from the theory of psychological externalism offered by Tyler Burge. Keywords: Nelson Goodman, Arthur Danto, textualism, interpretationism, func- tionalism, externalism. 1. What’s the use of a philosophical theory of the identity of a literary work of art – the theory that seeks necessary and suffi- cient conditions of the identity of a literary work, according to which the works X and Y are one and the same literary work of art? To be sure, such a theory can be of use to philosophers, if we admit that philosophers have a right to ponder even those questions whose import outside of philosophy is doubtful. How- ever, many of us think that if a philosophical theory sought an- swers to questions that never arose outside of philosophy, then the legitimacy of philosophy would somewhat suffer. If we wish to legitimate certain philosophical questions and theories that attempt to answer them, we must try to show their vital impor- tance beyond philosophy. In particular, if we wish to legitimate a philosophical interest in the identity of a literary work of art, we should start by examining the disciplines such as literary theory and criticism, in order to find out whether the questions concerning identity ever arise in them. Fortunately, for those of us to whom the practical import of philosophy matters, a cur- sory look into literary history and criticism suffices to demon- strate that the issue of identity lies at the very foundation of these disciplines. The students of literature have often to do with textual variations among whom they need to identify the text of the given work.1 In many cases, it’s not apparent that the work has only one, so to speak authentic, text. In practice, we see at least two sorts of cases. On the one hand, it happens that an author produces two or more texts that more or less differ from each other. This opens a room for de- bate about whether each of these texts is a different variant of the same literary work, or rather a different work. For example, the Czech writer Bohumil Hrabal used to constantly rewrite his works. He had various motivations: he wished to improve his works, but he also wanted to make sure, by means of a sort of self-censorship, that his works would get published in the Communist Czechoslovakia at all. When literary historians have access to both the self-censored text as well as the original text, they usually prefer the latter. As far as I know, both of these kinds of text are usually considered to be the texts of the same work. This means that the uncensored text is usually regarded as an authentic text of Hrabal’s work, yet the practice of literary history and criticism clearly admits that the work can survive more or less extensive tinkerings with the text. 1 The meaning of the term ‘text’ should not be regarded as transparent. As we shall see later, the definition of this term is a subject of philosophical dispute. It seems, however, that common sense works with a certain notion of text which can be summed up in two points. First, ‘text’ refers to a sequence of words and other linguistic symbols and these symbols are understood as both syntactic and semantic units. Second, the same text can exist in an unlimited number of exemplars or tokens. In practice, we are dealing with the tokens of a text, not with the text itself, which is, ontologically, a type.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    150 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us