Rethinking Althusser: Ideology, Dialectics, and Critical Social Theory

Rethinking Althusser: Ideology, Dialectics, and Critical Social Theory

1 Rethinking Althusser: Ideology, Dialectics, and Critical Social Theory John Grant Department of Politics Queen Mary, University of London [email protected] [email protected] Presented at the CPSA Annual Conference May 31-June 3 2005 University of Western Ontario, *Any use or reproduction of this work requires prior consent of the author* 2 Introduction This paper interrogates work by Louis Althusser within the larger context of an ongoing study into the efficacy of a dialectical approach to critical social theory. Althusser’s work occupies a productive place in twentieth century thought: it rejects the existential humanism of Sartre, while upholding the type of determinate political positions sometimes abandoned by poststructuralists such as Foucault or Derrida. My aim is to read Althusser predominantly against himself in order to rework and relocate his rendering of the dialectic. Althusser’s conception of the Marxist dialectic suffers, as I will show, from a number of conceptual deficiencies. Not only does it seem to reproduce the same type of economism he wanted to avoid, it overemphasizes the role of structural determinants. By refusing to employ any concept of the subject the conditions of dialectical analysis are lost, along with the possibility of accounting for political questions concerning experience and resistance. I believe that for social theory the real promise of Althusser’s thought lies in developing a more rigorous dialectical approach. The following is one way of envisioning the route this might take. 1) Refusing, unlike Althusser, to overemphasize the homogeneity of any ideological conjuncture, so that one can begin to identify the contradictory ways in which we are produced as subjects; 2) Maintaining the category of the subject over against Althusser’s strict anti- humanism, which allows one to recognize the movements and rhythms of a subject-object dialectic; 3) Althusser’s posthumously published work identifies what he terms “aleatory materialism.” It places significant importance on the ‘encounter’ as a moment of ontological becoming that is open and multiple. By emphasizing the singularity of every encounter 3 alongside the insights of (1) and (2), a dialectical approach is produced that allows the subject to identify the contradictory elements of its own, always incomplete, production. Finally, and most significantly, these elements can then be recast as points of resistance within a larger critical social theory. I - Althusser’s Marxist Dialectic Althusser’s project of constructing a so-called ‘scientific Marxism’ relies on using the concepts, according to him, that Marx developed as a way of understanding the historical development of social formations as a process without a subject. Often Althusser explicates his version of a Marxist dialectic by counterposing it to Hegel’s conception of dialectics. For example, the conception of an “overdetermined” contradiction is played off against “simple” one, which is based on the notion of an original unity that can be restored. Overdetermination implies that at any given moment society is characterized by multiple contradictions that are themselves the result of a multitude of different constituent elements (or at least more than two). The distinguishing feature of this complexity is a “structure in dominance” that assumes the principal role in organizing and articulating the specific form of any social whole (Althusser, 1969: 200- 02). Althusser calls the structure in dominance “the most profound characteristic of the Marxist dialectic” (1969: 206). This dominance is responsible for the uneven and overdetermined development of the structures that constitute the social whole, which is what delineates a specifically Marxist contradiction. In any social formation the economy is the dominant structure, although, famously, it is only dominant “in the last instance” (Althusser, 1969: 217). This feature of the dialectic is not only a reality for Althusser, but is required in order to “. escape the 4 arbitrary relativism of observable displacements by giving these displacements the necessity of a function” (Althusser and Balibar, 1970: 99). If the economy is only dominant in the last instance, this means that it is possible for a different structure to be dominant at any other instance, albeit for economic reasons. Indeed, Althusser goes so far as to claim that, “From the first moment to the last, the lonely hour of the ‘last instance’ never comes” (1969: 113). This is what invests overdetermination with such theoretical importance. At any given moment the structures that make up the social whole constitute a complex unity, which is governed by a specific structure in dominance. The productivity of overdetermination rests in the notion that the specific shape of a social formation is constantly developing (in response to the dominant structure), which requires an infinite return to the specific moment of conjuncture in order to articulate its form. The apparent tension in Althusser, between an emphasis on rather rigid structures and each singular social formation that they compose, is not necessarily as great as it might seem. There is a certain implicit, continual movement, from one position to the other, even if for now the concern with structures seems to take priority. The explanatory priority of structures cannot be understood apart from Althusser’s rejection of humanism and the category of the subject, which he identifies as a major difference between the Hegelian and Marxist dialectics. Althusser invested great energy in his opposition to Hegelian and existentialist Marxists like Herbert Marcuse and Jean-Paul Sartre, whom he saw as humanists trapped in a philosophy of the subject and consciousness (see Althusser, 1976: 99, 188). The following quotation introduces Althusser’s notion of ideology, and helps to explain why humanism is an ideological concept. In ideology men do indeed express, not the relation between them and their conditions of existence, but the way they live the relation between them and their conditions of existence: this presupposes both a real and an ‘imaginary’, ‘lived’ relation . In ideology 5 the real relation is inevitably invested in the imaginary relation, a relation that expresses a will (conservative, conformist, reformist or revolutionary), a hope or a nostalgia, rather than describing a reality (1969: 233-34). The humanist idea of the subject contains what Althusser calls “the theoretical characters cast in this ideological scenario,” which include “the philosophical Subject (the philosophizing consciousness), the scientific Subject (the knowing consciousness), and the empirical Subject (the perceiving consciousness) . .” (1970: 54-5). Althusser is rejecting any notion of a constitutive subject that acts as the source of its own thoughts and actions. The humanist subject is ideological because it imagines that it controls its surroundings, that its relationship to its conditions of existence is shaped, first and foremost, by its ability to make unrestricted and transparent personal choices. Further, humanist notions of the subject necessarily rely on some idea of human essence, and therefore origin. To wit, humans have an original essence from which they are currently estranged or alienated; our foremost considerations, then, must be devoted to reestablishing conditions that allow this essence to become knowable, and flourish. This is the basis on which Marx’s early work is often judged. Althusser’s well-known claim is that there is an epistemological break in Marx’s work around 1845 (and in The German Ideology specifically) that signalled the end of his flirtations with the humanist anthropology of Hegel and Feuerbach.1 Quite simply, when it comes to understanding social relations and change, the individual, or the category of the subject, is an inadequate unit of analysis (indeed an ideological one) compared with, say, classes, or the mode and relations of production,. Political and historical change, then, must be thought as a process without a subject. In typically provocative fashion, Althusser writes that Marx’s “theoretical anti-humanism” constitutes a philosophical revolution. “It is impossible to know anything about men except on 6 the precondition that the philosophical (theoretical) myth of man is reduced to ashes” (1969: 229).2 This has direct implications for the dialectic. While Althusser’s concept of overdetermination contains a specific understanding of complex contradiction between structural relations, it can no longer be articulated using the concepts of subject and object. Because he thinks the socio-political field as a series of objects, any claim to knowledge must be posed “. in terms which exclude any recourse to the ideological solution contained in the ideological characters Subject and Object, or to the mutual mirror-recognition structure, in the closed circle of which they move” (1970: 55). Althusser is hostile to any counter-argument that there is always a mediating term or element that displaces the simple subject-object dichotomy (subjectivity and labour are two terms that played this role for Hegel). “The concept of mediation is invested with one last role: the magical provision of post-stations in the empty space between theoretical principles and the ‘concrete’, as bricklayers make a chain to pass bricks” (Althusser and Balibar, 1970: 63). The existence of subject and object as theoretical terms cannot be made more real by making it look as if they interact with actual concrete

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    21 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us